Voltaire Lecture for the British Humanist
Association, KingÕs College London, December 13th 2001.
NB. Written in 2001
this paper contains some sceptical remarks on, amongst other things, the fear
of global warming. It no longer represents my views on this matter exactly, but
it does illustrate a certain space between public perceptions and the scientific
measurements they are supposedly based upon, so I have let it stand, regardless
of whether in the intervening years the public perception has proved correct,
and the scientific measurements have begun finally to accord with it. This may
well be so, although it is salutary to ask the question how often the media
quote anything they please—the arrival of migrating ducks, the sprouting
of tulips, rainfall in London—rather than the temperature of the
troposphere, as ÔevidenceÕ of the phenomenon. In 2001 I believe there was no
close accord between the perceptions and the measurements.
Does Relativism Matter?
September 11th, we are told, changed the world.
That may be true, at least because it has changed how many people perceive the
world. And a change in peoplesÕ ideas is a change in the world. We should not,
however, expect many of those changes to be for the better, since it must be a
general rule that when people are angry and afraid their ideas and actions go
worse. In 1726, we may recall, Voltaire was exiled from France to London,
where he was amazed and enchanted by the freedoms of the English. He was lucky
not to be exiled here in the twenty-first century, and still less to the United
States of America. As a foreign national, he would now risk indefinite
arbitrary detention, the abrogation of habeas corpus, a secret hearing with no
right of representation, and a right of review only by the same tribunal. In
the USA he could face state murder: the death penalty by majority vote of a
secret military tribunal from which there would be no appeal.
But one change since September 11th, perhaps
for the better, is that more people seem prepared to think about meanings: the
meaning of a society, the meaning of a civilization, the meaning of toleration
and the meaning of respect, the meaning of standards and of values. Before
September 11th such thoughts might have seemed airy-fairy, unBritish, the
playground of the effete chattering classes. Since then, it is no longer quite
so unfashionable to sit up and listen.
Unfortunately however, the voices the public hear have been less than
impressive. The debate in this country, and still more in the United States,
too often aligns itself around a simple polarity. Are we to be religious? In
that case, it is assumed, there are real truths, real standards, real values
which we can use to guide our own behaviour and that of others. Or, are we to
be atheists or agnostics? In that case, it is again assumed, there are no real
truths or standards or values, and we fall prey to a variety of ailments:
materialism, cynicism, nihilism, relativism.
There is almost nothing that is right about
this way of drawing up the issue, and the philosophical tradition has abundant
resources to show that there is almost nothing right about it. Yet this
tradition seldom gets its voice heard. It is not allowed on Thought for the
Day, where bishops and rabbis and mullahs are given their daily,
publicly-subsidized, advertising time. But let us start with the tiny bit that
is right. This is the association of religious belief with dogma, intolerance,
and illiberalism, and the corresponding association of atheism and agnosticism
with liberalism and toleration. The very word ÔsectarianÕ alerts us to this,
and a religion is only a sect with an army. The Òreal standardsÓ of religions,
as Voltaire saw all too often in his own lifetime, are those of
authoritarianism and separatism, of conformism within and persecution without.
It would be easy to fill a volume with the
horrors of monotheistically inspired ethics: the ethics of the sadistic God.
But the only charge I shall press is this. The first and all too often the last
virtue of any of the monotheistic religions is faith, because it is faith that
holds the flock together, and defines Us, inside, against Them, outside. But
faith is not a virtue. Faith is credulity: the condition of believing things
for which there is no reason. It is a vice, and it inevitably encourages other
vices, including hypocrisy and fanaticism. It needs to be said, loudly, that it
makes no more sense to talk of faith-based schools or faith-based education
than it does to talk of superstition-based science or terror-based debate.
There have, of course, been educated and enlightened people who profess faiths,
but their education and enlightenment happened despite their superstitions, and
not because of them. Faith is by its essence the enemy of education, which
teaches people to base beliefs on reason and on reason alone.
We need look no further back than the
mid-nineteenth century to remember that even in England, when they could, the
churches stifled freedom of thought. When Richard Cobden, the great reformer,
looked back on his campaign for public schooling, he said:
I took the repeal of the Corn Laws as light
amusement compared with the difficult task of inducing the priests of all
denominations to agree to suffer the people to be educated
But this is not how the popular debate lines
up. Partly this is because in one of the most bare-faced takeover bids in the
history of thought, the western churches have pretended to take on the mantle
of liberalism and toleration themselves, going into happy-clappy denial about
their dreadful centuries of internal and external persecutions. It is declining
power that forces upon them these pacific and ecumenical gestures, just as,
conversely, the increasing power of Islam aligned so notably with increasing military
and persecuting tendencies during the life of the prophet. Islam at least tries
to preserve consistency, so that when in Sura 9.5 Muslims are told to Òkill
unbelievers wherever you find them,Ó the consensus is that this time, late in
MuhammedÕs life, the archangel Gabriel meant exactly what is said, and that
earlier verses counselling toleration are thereby cancelled. It is of course
only by a very narrow escape that it is still legal to say aloud that such a
doctrine is hateful.
But toleration, which is often, although
not always, a good thing, is not the same as relativism, which is never a good
thing; and it is vital to understand the difference. In the intellectual world,
toleration is the disposition to fight opinion only with opinion: in other words,
to protect freedom of speech, and to confront divergence of opinion with open
critical reflection rather than suppression or force. The first great champion
of toleration in this sense was John Locke, and his successors included not
only famous liberals such as John Stuart Mill, but men with a rather more
direct impact on human affairs, such as Thomas Jefferson. Toleration entered
political life with the Enlightenment. It is a characteristically secular
virtue: there has never been and never will be a theocracy that can
wholeheartedly applaud it. For the religious mind, many sayings are not to be
assessed at the bar of truth or falsity, but at that of blasphemy, and to hold
that a person blasphemes is to hold that that personÕs sayings at least, and the
person for preference, must be suppressed.
Toleration gives us the dictum attributed to
Voltaire, that I disapprove of what you say, but I will defend to the death
your right to say it. Relativism, by contrast, chips away at our right to
disapprove of what anybody says. Relativism names a loose cluster of attitudes,
but the central message is that there are no asymmetries of reason and
knowledge, objectivity and truth. There are two relativistic mantras: ÒWho is
to say?Ó (who is to say which opinion is better?) and ÒThatÕs just your
opinionÓ (your opinion is on all fours with any other). There are only
different views, each true ÒforÓ those who hold them. Relativism in this sense
goes beyond counselling that we must try to understand those whose opinions are
different. It is not only that we must try to understand them, but also that we
must recognize a symmetry of standing. Their opinions Òdeserve the same
respectÓ as our own. So, at the limit, we may have western values, but they
have others; we have a western view of the universe, they have theirs; we have
western science, they have traditional science; and so on.
There have been many philosophical attempts to
refute relativism, beginning perhaps with PlatoÕs encounter with sophists such
as Gorgias or opponents such as Theodorus in the Theaetetus. Theodorus defends ProtagorasÕs
doctrine that Man is the Measure of All Things, which Socrates takes to imply
relativism. The central tactic Socrates uses is to query whether the
relativistic doctrine applies to itself. If it does not, then it seems that
there is at least one non-relative, absolute truth. If it does, then indeed
relativism may be true for Protagoras, but remains untrue for Socrates and the
rest of us who agree with him. Here is Socrates:
Éthere is a second consequence, which is
exquisite. In saying that everyone believes what is the case, he is conceding
the truth of beliefs which oppose his own; In other words, he is conceding the
truth of the opinion that he is wrong.
Socrates implies that this is a problem, indeed
an ÔexquisiteÕ problem for Protagoras. However, it is not very clear what kind
of problem it is. A determined Protagoras seems well able to bite the bullet,
since Protagoras is only conceding that it is true for Socrates that he, Protagoras,
is wrong, and by ProtagorasÕs own account that can coexist perfectly happily
with whatever he believed in the first place. William James says as much two
millennia later:
But can there be self-stultification in urging
any account whatever of truth? Can the definition ever contradict the deed?
ÔTruth is what I feel like sayingÕ—suppose that to be the definition.
ÔWell, I feel like saying that, and I want you to feel like saying it, and
shall continue to say it until I get you to agree.Õ Whatever truth may be said
to be, that is the kind of truth which the saying can be held to carry. The temper which a saying may comport in an
extra logical matter.
By the temper James means the force or zeal or
conviction that the relativist brings to his position. Plato, together with
modern followers such as Thomas Nagel, holds that force and zeal can only
coexist with belief that what you say is true, meaning absolutely true, true
for everybody here and elsewhere, now and forever. Plato and Nagel agree with
Hilaire Belloc, in having no time for the:
Don different from those regal dons
With hearts of gold and lungs of bronze
Who shout and bang and roar and bawl
The absolute across the hall.
James, and Protagoras by contrast, allow force
or zeal or conviction to coexist with the relativistic doctrine.
Once this is the debate, it is not at all obvious who wins. But I want to
highlight something curious about both positions, and hence about the shape of
the debate about relativism. It is as if each participant sees talk of truth,
(together with its partners reason, proof, evidence, probability) as something
with which we clothe ourselves, an extra layer which we like to put on. Then the
absolutist thinks that truth gives us, as it were, clothing of state. Truth and
the rest are the symbols of authority. Like professional judges, until we don
them we are not suitably clothed, not speaking with the full ex cathedra
dignity we need. By contrast, the relativist sees the clothing as a mask. We
put it on in order to disguise the naked realities of power and persuasion,
rhetoric and ideology, spin and agendas.
In this is the landscape, the two sides are
very apt to talk past each other. I illustrate this in my book Being Good. There I tell a story about this
which I very much like, and at the risk of boring anyone who has read that
book, I would like to tell it again here. It concerns a friend of mine, who was
present at a high-powered ethics institute which had put on a forum in which
representatives of the great religions held a panel. First the Buddhist talked
of the ways to calm, the mastery of desire, the path of enlightenment, and the
panellists all said ÔWow, terrific, if that works for you thatÕs greatÕ. Then
the Hindu talked of the cycles of suffering and birth and rebirth, the
teachings of Krishna and the way to release, and they all said ÔWow, terrific,
if that works for you thatÕs greatÕ. And so on, until the Catholic priest
talked of the message of Jesus Christ, the promise of salvation and the way to
life eternal, and they all said ÔWow, terrific, if that works for you thatÕs
greatÕ. And he thumped the table and shouted: ÔNo! ItÕs not a question of it if
works for me! ItÕs the true word of the living God, and if you donÕt believe it
youÕre all damned to Hell!Õ
And they all said: ÔWow, terrific, if that works for you thatÕs greatÕ.
The point here is that the relativist will only
hear the shouting and roaring and bawling of the Absolute in his own way. His
ear is cocked so as to hear only ideology or politics, not the intended claim
to absolute truth. It is no good insisting upon truth, objectivity, or reason
when ears are so cocked, for such ears only hear more of the same, but louder.
Incidentally, we might note that while in this story the relativists are of the
happy-clappy disposition, they are not always so. Those who think of claims to
truth and objectivity as masks do not always relapse into happy-clappy pluralism.
They may find the masks hateful, and are probably equally likely to lapse into
snarling cynicism; this is particularly so when it is supposed that the appeal
to objectivity and the rest disguises colonial or patriarchal or other takeover
bids.
But should this be the landscape? I said that in talk of truth and the rest,
one side sees robes of state, while the other side sees only masks. But suppose
each of them is wrong? The shared assumption is that talk of truth and the rest
is a kind of optional extra, about which the absolutist is unashamed but about
which the relativist is modestly diffident. Yet this assumption is false. This
was pointed out both by the great German philosopher of language, Frege, and by
the Cambridge philosopher Frank Ramsey. They point out, in effect, that in the
ordinary practise of advancing and then either accepting or rejecting claims,
we do not raise the temperature by talking of truth. If someone tells me that
the price of gas is rising, and I reply ÔthatÕs trueÕ or ÔthatÕs rightÕ, I am
simply expressing agreement. I am not adding an extra pat on the back to the
original remark. If I donÕt believe the original remark, I can say that it is
not true, or that we have to wait and see. If I do this, then we have to set
about determining whether the price of gas is rising, and it may turn out
either way. We do not in addition have a different question on our plate,
namely, whether it is true that the price of gas is rising. Our only problem is
set by what we say. It is the issue that is the issue, not anything further.
How does this affect the relativist? Protagoras said that man is the measure of
all things. Well, suppose the issue is a nice one of measurement. What time is
high tide at Newhaven tomorrow? I could have an opinion about that. But unless
I have done my homework, it would not be likely to be reliable. Homework here
means consulting tide-tables. Or, if it is my business to produce timetables it
may mean something more direct, such doing some calculations, or perhaps going
down to Newhaven with a measuring rod and a clock. It is true, of course, that
a particularly awkward customer may dislike this measurement process, and it is
open to him to argue for another. Like any human process, even simple
measurement is fallible and may be conducted more or less well. But at the end
of the day either the water stops rising at a given time, or it does not. Tide
tables have their prestige not because of social and political machinations,
but because they are reliable. Were there a competition, a market-place for
rival tables, success would eventually winnow out those that work from those
that do not. Hence, Protagoras got only part of the way. Man indeed lies behind
the measurement, but that does not mean we can conduct the measurement any
which way. If we do, our ships go aground, and our projects are thwarted.
When I said that the issue is the issue, this is what I meant. To make an
assertion at all is to put a view into public space, up for acceptance or
rejection. That public space will be replete with more-or-less articulate
norms: things that count for acceptance or rejection. In the case of the height
of the tide, those norms determine what counts as an answer and what counts as
a reason for an answer. There is no question either of putting on a mantle of
robes of state, or of seeing the same mantle as nothing but a mask. There is
just the question of when it is high tide at Newhaven, and our best methods for
settling it.
Here we meet a sudden gestalt switch. We find
that the relativist, at first blush a tolerant, relaxed, laid-back, pluralistic
kind of person can suddenly seem to be a kind of monster. If I say that high
tide this afternoon at Newhaven is at two oÕclock, I do not want to be met with
the patronizing response that if that works for me thatÕs great. That might be
appropriate if I had just said something that strongly suggested I was mad, or
if I were uttering the sentence in something like the spirit of a poetry
recital, not as something to be accepted or rejected, but perhaps as something
to be tasted and savoured. But this is not what I am doing when I voice some
commitment. I expect my audience to engage with the commitment itself. To hear
my saying just as a symptom, perhaps of my class or race or history, is failing
to do this. It is regarding me as a patient. It is to think of me, in Peter
StrawsonÕs wonderful phrase, as someone to be Òmanaged or handled or cured or
trainedÓ. It is relativism itself that is here dehumanising.
As an aside, I should mention that this is why
the Òscience warsÓ generate such heat. The science wars arose when scientists
found sociologists and historians of science apparently rubbing a lot of the
bloom from the scientific enterprise itself. In good relativistic fashion the
sociologists and historians and cultural critics bracketed scienceÕs claims to
objectivity and truth, and regarded the enterprise purely in an anthropological
spirit. Scientists became a tribe whose structures of authority, of peer group
acceptance, of prestige and funding, were to be investigated in the same spirit
as those of the medicine men of the Azande or the Navaho. In particular the
historian or sociologist had to eschew any issue of truth or falsity. In the
words of the so-called Strong Program:
Our equivalence postulates that all beliefs are
on a par with one another with respect to the causes of their credibility. It
is not that all beliefs are equally true or equally false, but that regardless
of truth and falsity the fact of their credibility is to be seen as equally
problematic. The position we shall defend is that the incidence of all beliefs
without exception calls for empirical investigation and must be accounted for
by finding the specific, local causes of this credibility. This means that
regardless of whether the sociologist evaluates a belief as true or rational,
or as false and irrational, he must search for the causes of its
credibilityÉ.all these questions can and should be answered without regard to
the status of the belief as it is judged and evaluated by the sociologistÕs own
standards.
This might sound innocent enough: merely a
clinical or detached standpoint of objectivity. But from the standpoint of the
scientist it is outrageous in exactly the way that I have been describing
relativism as outrageous. From the practitionersÕ point of view, all beliefs
are not on a par with respect to the causes of their credibility. The reason an
astronomer believes that Jupiter has four moons is he has seen or calculated or
inferred from other data that Jupiter has four moons. The reason he issues
these tide tables is that calculations, shown to be reliable by centuries of
experience, enable him to issue them. In successful science there is no gap, of
the kind Barnes and Bloor insert, between the causes of belief and its truth.
In other words, the posture of neutrality means that the sociologist appears
like the kind of nightmare psychoanalyst who looks for the causes of my
believing that there is butter in the fridge in my childhood or my parents or
my sex life—everywhere except in the fridge. From my point of view there
is only one reason why I believe there is butter in the fridge, which is that I
went and saw it was there. If the psychoanalyst ÒbracketsÓ that fact then
nothing he says can be of value to describing me. In other words, we can only
bracket questions of truth when what is to be explained is delusion and error,
or a remarkable selection of one truth from others, or in some other way an
aspect of the enterprise which is inexplicable by the standards of
truth-seeking. Thinking that scientific results and theories are inexplicable
by the standards of truth-seeking is seeing the scientific endeavour as more
akin to a poetry reading or a piece of political rhetoric than an investigation
into moons, and tides, and for that matter the place of the butter.
Of course, this is not to deny that science, again like all human enterprises,
can go wrong. A proper modesty is always in place: the scientist need not be
bent on shouting, banging, roaring and bawling. Nor is it to deny that patterns
of enquiry and interest will often be set by outside forces: military funding,
drug company money, or political expediency. But in spite of these suspicious
partners, the particular glory of science is its self-corrective nature, to
which I shall return in time. Meanwhile the emotions involved in the science
wars bear full witness to the dehumanising nature of the enterprise of
explaining the shape our minds take without caring to enter into the reasons
why they take the shape they do.
Many of you will be thinking that this is all
very well when it comes to simple physical measurements like the height or time
of the tide. But can we say the same when values swim into view? It is
essential that we can. If I hold that capital punishment ought not to be
allowed, and you hold that it can be, we disagree. Once more the issue is the
issue: should we or should we not allow capital punishment? We might find the
issue hard, and we might find ourselves entangled in uncertainties when we
pursue it. We will need to think about things like the rights of members of a
state, the rights of the state, the consequences of actions, the emotion of
revenge, and many others. That only shows that it is not a simple issue. But as
we pursue it, the relativistic voice (whoÕs to say? ThatÕs just your opinion!)
is once more purely a distraction. It is we who are trying to say, and when we
voice an opinion we try to put it in such a light that it is not ÒjustÓ our
opinion, but an opinion with weight behind it. When I voice my opposition to
the abrogation of civil liberties, here and in the United States, it is not
ÒjustÓ my opinion. It is at least the opinion of centuries of jurisprudence,
and the rule of law. If we like, it is the voice of humanityÕs bitter
experience with Inquisitions and secret hearings and the power of the
executive. When I say such things, just as surely as when I talk of high tide,
my opinion is put into public space for acceptance or rejection or debate. I do
not voice my mind in the spirit of a poetry reading or still less as a way of
manifesting medical symptoms. I voice it with the intention that we come to one
mind about this, and this is the way I would like our one mind to be. Given
that this is the project, the relativistic voice merely as a nuisance or a
distraction, and can subside into the shadows.
We still have to be sure of our epistemology.
We want our opinions to deserve assent, which means finding considerations in
their favour to which, we hope, reasonable people must listen. Here, philosophy
can also help. Principally, I want to argue, it steers us between exaggerated
hopes and exaggerated pessimism. The exaggerated hope is for something akin to
proof. We would like a demonstration that one opinion is correct: a
demonstration to which everybody must listen, on pain of forfeiting any claim
to rationality. In ethics, this Holy Grail was sought most successfully by
Immanuel Kant, who found it in the formula that I should act only in such a way
that I can also will that the maxim should become a universal law.
Few doubt that Kant has seized on something
important, and indeed something that structures a great deal of our practical
reasonings. Indeed, it is implicit in the very notion of the public space of
reason that claims can be assessed from a common point of view. A powerful way
of making someone worry about our patriotic anti-terrorist laws is to ask how
they would like it if British or American citizens faced the possibility of
such tribunals whenever they travelled abroad. It is, indeed, precisely because
religious conviction suppresses that procedure—since to the true believer
the project of accommodating the point of view of the unbeliever remains a sin—that
religion remains the greatest enemy of ethics. Nevertheless in the end I
believe we have to judge that Kant fails. There is no proof or algorithm
waiting to drum dissidents—such as religious people or patriotic people
brainwashed into thinking in terms of an Us and a Them—into the ranks of
the virtuous.
But we do not have to recoil from this into any
kind of scepticism. Human nature and human need fills the gap that reason alone
cannot fill. The common enterprise of practical reasoning has plenty of data.
We know when life is going well and when it is going badly, and we know what to
admire and what to reject. The virtues of courage and intelligence, patience
and concern, are virtues the world over. It is usually not the values that are
difficult, but the practical problem of how best to implement them.
There is a final point about relativism that
needs to be understood. Frege and Ramsey show us that truth is not a good point
of focus. For to wonder whether p is true is no more than to wonder whether p. And the meaning of p, all by itself, determines the
norms of assent and verification. If p is a scientific claim, the procedures of
science will be needed. If it is a historical claim, the procedures of the
library and the archive. If those procedures are themselves contested then we
have to step back and discuss methods of inquiry, trying to line our procedures
up with our own best sense of our own reliability. If the issue is ethical or
political, we summon up our best understandings of what it is for life to go
well or badly, admirably or distressingly.
But all this leaves space for some to worry
about the concepts that may be used in framing an issue. The vocabulary in
which we frame our issues, they point out, is our vocabulary. Our eyes and ears are
twenty-first century eyes and ears. And then the thought may arise that there
could be other vocabularies, other concepts or ways of organizing our mental
responses to the world, shaping other perspectives. And then from those other
perspectives perhaps our concerns will seem primitive or regrettable, easily
by-passed, fogged up by mists that engulf our particular time and place.
Perhaps our concepts are (merely) Western, or patriarchal, or bourgeois or scientistic.
Perhaps we are trapped in our own histories, prisoners of forces of which we
know next to nothing. Some contemporary philosophers, notably Richard Rorty,
believing himself to voice a tradition stretching back to Dewey and
Wittgenstein, think the only response to this thought is a kind of weightless
irony; a disengagement from issues that, one day, may seem not to have been
worth taking seriously. Rorty thus takes the same view of the landscape as
Plato or Nagel, but, fearing distance from the absolute, feels unable to shout
or bang or roar or bawl, or indeed say anything at all except with the ironic
snigger attached.
Once more, however, the tradition enables us to
put more backbone into the picture than this. The weakness in this conceptual
relativism is its transition from a bare possibility to a piece of practical
advice. The premise of bare possibility is fine but weak. There is, we should
admit, a bare possibility of better ways of looking at things. There is the
possibility of improving our ways of thinking, just as there is the possibility
of getting worse. But what is the implication of that? While improvement
remains a bare possibility, we have no option but to stick with what we have.
There may be a future in which people do not sail, or sailors do not need to
take account of tides. But that is not our world, and in the meantime those who
sail the seas need an answer to the time of high tide. Treating the question,
or its answer, with light irony is foolish. There may come a time when scientists
no longer think in quantum mechanical terms. But meanwhile there are lasers and
scanners and cameras and computers to design, and quantum mechanics is the only
game in town. Equally there may come a world in which political currency
changes, and our ways of living are no longer discussed in terms of equality,
justice, deprivation, resources, or education or freedom or oppression.
Meanwhile there are scholars sentenced to death for saying things that are
true, women who are denied education or security or medical aid, we have
assaults on our freedoms, and rampant inequalities of resources and
opportunities. The idea that we should not care about any of that just because
one day we might come to think in other terms would be ludicrous if it were not
tragic.
I begin my ending by bringing in a cousin of relativism, and one perhaps more
associated with Voltaire himself, which is scepticism. In the public mind they
are not sharply separated, I suspect, since the relativist, like the sceptic,
is supposed to suspend judgement in places where other, more red-blooded
people, like BellocÕs dons, want belief and conviction. But in reality they are
diametrically opposed. According to the relativist belief and conviction fly
out of the window because truth is, as it were, too cheap to care about. There
is too much of it about: your truth, his truth, and my truth. For the sceptic
belief and conviction fly out of the window because truth is too rare. We
cannot care about it because we cannot find it; we cannot even search for it
because we cannot tell when we are getting closer.
Unlike the relativistic frame of mind that of the sceptic is often admirable.
The relativist reflection, we have seen, is dehumanising. Its attitude,
including its light irony, is the stance of someone above the fray, someone who
has seen through the debates and engagements of ordinary participants. But this
stance, I have argued, is demeaning and impoverished, a mere distraction from
whatever issue concerns us. By contrast the sceptic makes no attempt to bypass
or sideline the issue. The issue is the issue, and so is truth. It is just that
according to the sceptic, we cannot find the truth. We must moderate our
opinions, confess to our ignorance, avoid conviction and dogma because we
recognize the inadequacies of our investigations or our methods.
The British, fortunately, have strong sceptical leanings, which is partly why
the roaring and bawling of the present government is so despised. Americans by
contrast have a natural appetite for belief. According to one account I have
read, it is not only that around 90% believe in the literal truth of
Christianity, but 49% believe that people are sometimes possessed by devils,
and three and a half million believe themselves to have been abducted, at some time or
another, by aliens. This is disturbing, for none of those beliefs are
guaranteed to remain inert, especially when times are fearful: we may remember
those unfortunates a year or two ago, who believed that the Hale Bopp comet was
a spiritual recycling facility for dead Californians, and killed themselves so
as to go to join it. As Voltaire also said, those who can make you believe
absurdities can make you commit atrocities.
Nevertheless, scepticism has its limitations, and I would like to close by
exploring one of them. Let me start with a complaint. Earlier this year the
great American philosopher Willard van Orman Quine died. His death prompted an
ignorant and shameful article in the Times by their journalist Simon Jenkins,
lamenting that Quine was the kind of philosopher who lived and wrote remote
from the everyday: a typical example of the useless intellectual. And indeed,
unlike the Balliol dons we have already met, Quine trumpeted few absolutes. Yet
neither was he a sceptic. So what good did he do?
Well, Quine was probably the most important
theorist of knowledge of the latter half of the twentieth century. He gave a
subtle, original, and comprehensive theory of the proper process whereby
experience should be transmuted into theory. Quine knew that none of the
avenues to knowledge is simple, or infallible, or immune to endless revision
and question. Neither the senses, nor testimony, nor history nor theory nor
reason itself gives us bedrock. In his favourite metaphor, borrowed from the
positivist Otto Neurath, we are like sailors condemned to rebuild our boats at
sea. No part is immune to critical inspection, and each part can be replaced,
but we must stand on other parts as we do it. The only rational process is to
discover what works, and to warp our scientific heritage as cautiously as
possible to cope with the recalcitrant experiences nature brings our way. This
is the way of science, with its virtues of observation and experiment, of
conjecture and refutation, of open debate. Science should be seens as a
Darwinian process whereby a plurality of theories compete for credibility, and
only the fittest survive, perhaps only for one lifetime, in the endless process
of self-correction.
In saying these things Quine was partly echoing
the American pragmatist C. S. Peirce, famous for the much-criticized definition
of truth as the opinion which the progress of science is fated to converge on
in the long run. But the long run is only an imaginary focus: the process is
itself guaranteed to yield improvement at each step on the way. It is because
he believed in this process that Quine was not a sceptic.
There is, however a place where a different set
of processes enter. Peirce, and Quine are perhaps apt to describe science as a
kind of self-enclosed enterprise, driven by an inner logic, and needing no
support from its surroundings. But it is of the utmost importance to see that
this is false, and false in many dimensions. It is most obviously false because
institutional science needs support. It needs the leisure of inquiry, which in
turn needs investment. It is false too because the whole Darwinian process only
works given virtues of integrity, communication, toleration, and
open-mindedness. Science could only flourish when religion lost the power to
stifle those virtues, and its still cannot flourish where religion or other
forces retain that power. Science, in other words, needs an entire cultural and
political matrix in which to grow properly, and nothing in that matrix can be
taken for granted.
We see small examples of this in particular
parts of the scientific enterprise, perhaps most notably medicine. The wise,
Hume told us, lend a very academic faith to any report that flatters the
passions of the reporter. Few of us are taken in when the American psychiatric
association voted to medicalize naughtiness, inventing instead attention
deficit disorder, and so opening the way for one in seven children in the
country to be regularly and profitably prescribed Ritalin, a class-A drug with
sedative effects. When the government here refused a foot and mouth inquiry,
they instead appointed old friends and colleagues to report on the virtuous
conduct of old friends and colleagues, and HumeÕs dictum predicts the way such
an ÒinquiryÓ will be received. More insidious cases of mass hallucination
probably depend in the first instance on institutional needs of particular
sciences. So, for instance, The United Nations Intergovernmental Panel on
Climate Change has relentlessly issued graphs and reports testifying to the
imminent and catastrophic effects of global warming. For the scientists on the
panel such claims justify further funding, not to mention increased
institutional power, computer time, and first-class air travel to exotic
conferences. The passion that makes us receive these reports, like those of
other environmental disasters, so avidly is, I suppose, that of guilt. For
there is in fact only the poorest evidence of any atmospheric warming, and
excellent evidence that there is either none or next to none, just as there is
no evidence of rising sea levels and none of increased climate violence (the
poor evidence for derives from arbitrarily scattered surface measurements; the
stronger evidence against derives from satellite data that covers virtually the
entire globe, and meteorological balloons).
My purpose here is not to qualify my message by
belittling science. On the contrary the data are the result of painstaking,
excellent, impeccable science. But a public statement can sit on the top of a
mountain of science without adequately reflecting that science. It is the
public statements, whether of the American Psychiatric Society, the Government,
or the Intergovernmental Panel on Climate Change that need to be taken with a
generous pinch of salt. Hume also quotes with approval a saying of La
Rochefoucault that there are many things in which the world wishes to be
deceived. The religious impulse is one manifestation of this truth. But another
is the impact of emotions, including fear and guilt, upon belief, and this is
the mechanism that leads us to receive messages of doom and disaster with our
critical faculties asleep. And this brings us back to a question close to that
of relativism, which is the issue of confidence with which I shall end.
The west, it is sadly said, has lost confidence in the Enlightenment. It is
quite common to see intellectuals state as a fact that the Enlightenment
project has been tried and failed. This is a lie. There never was one single
Enlightenment project, and of the Enlightenment projects that there were, many
have succeeded beyond the wildest hopes of their proponents. The Enlightenment
provided the matrix I have talked of, in which scientific enterprises could
flourish. Now, our understanding of the world is better because of physical
science. Our understanding of ourselves is better because of biological
science. We live longer, and we feed ourselves better, and ÔweÕ here includes
not only people in first world countries, but countless people in the third
world. We look after the environment better, and in time we will manage our own
numbers better. Outside the theocracies of the east more people have more
freedoms and enjoy more education, more opportunities and may even have more
rights than ever before. We owe this progress entirely to the culture forged,
in the west, by Bacon and Locke, Hume and Voltaire, Newton and Darwin. Humanism
is the belief that humanity need not be ashamed of itself, and these are its
great examples. They show us that we need not regard knowledge as impious, or
ignorance as desirable, and we need not see blind faith as anything other than
blind.