This paper is
published in James Dreier, ed. Recent Debates in Moral Theory. (Blackwell, 2006) All references should
be made to, and from, the published version.
Hume said that the
distinct boundaries and offices of reason and taste are easily ascertained,
including under the heading of ÔtasteÕ the moral sentiments.[1]
Alas, he proved over-optimistic. I doubt if any question in moral theory has
proved more vexatious. The area is confounded by difficulties over the
identification of attitudes and beliefs, over the distinction between senses of
the word ÔreasonÕ that sentimentalists can admit from those they must deny,
over the relation between properties and concepts, over the metaphysics of the
categorical imperative, and over much else besides. In this brief essay I can
therefore not attempt a full-scale defence of sentimentalism. I shall simply
defend the theory against various recent assaults, one of which is mounted in
Samuel KersteinÕs defence of rationalism in this debate. My impression is that
Kerstein does not stand alone, but is a spokesman for a whole phalanx of
people, perhaps calling themselves ÔKantiansÕ, who would sympathize with his
assault, or at least fail to understand how a sentimentalist could withstand
it.
It is fortunate,
then, that the misunderstanding that permeates KersteinÕs treatment of
sentimentalism is highly visible, and I shall concentrate on one particularly
exposed passage. After giving an account of my own neo-Humean description of
the emotions and attitudes that underlie our propensity to go in for ethics and
morals, he considers the issue of justice to strangers or outsiders. He writes
that on my view:
It is a personÕs
displeasing sentiments, ones such as unease or shame, that form the basis of
her obligation to acquire the character trait of being just to strangers, or at
least to act in a way that a person with this trait would act.
He continues:
This last point is
crucial to the issue of whether sentimentalism coheres with the idea that there
are categorical imperatives. On this account the basis for an agentÕs
obligation to do something is a displeasing sentiment she has when, after
taking the Òcommon point of view,Ó she contemplates her not doing it or,
perhaps, her not possessing the character of someone who would do itÉIf an
agent does not have this sentiment, then she has no obligation. Of course, if
an agent has no obligation to perform a certain action, then a principle
commanding that action does not count as a categorical imperative. For it
belongs to the concept of a categorical imperative that everyone within its
scope is obligated to do what it enjoins. So in order for sentimentalism to
ground a particular categorical imperative, each and every person, after taking
the common point of view and so forth, must have a displeasing sentiment
towards not doing what the imperative commands.
So, although
Kerstein also chides me for failing to answer the question of how moral
obligations Ôstem fromÕ the processes I have described, he supposes that such
an account, were it provided, would inevitably suppose that people without the
sentiments are free of the obligation: the ÔbasisÕ of her obligation is a
sentiment, so that Ôif an agent does not have this sentiment, then she has no
obligationÕ. In a similar vein he imagines someone with no sympathy for members
of some minority within his society, and says that Ôon BlackburnÕs
sentimentalist account, you have at this point no obligation to refrain from
abusing the minorityÕ.
And then,
unsurprisingly, he can go on to point out that there are legions of unhappily
bad Samaritans, and what I called foreign-office knaves, when I was stressing
and lamenting the same sad fact about humanity. These people do not have the
appropriate sentiments. Hence, Kerstein concludes, for the sentimentalist,
there are people who lie under no obligation to universal justice. Hence, there
are no categorical imperatives, for the categorical imperative embraces
everyone.
Whatever else is
to be said about it, we should notice that this argument is remarkable for its
scope. It can be directed not only against sentimentalism, but against any
theory that seeks to explain our moral capacities in terms of contingent and
potentially variable facets of human nature: language, culture, upbringing,
acquired Ôsecond natureÕ, and so on. Even reason, insofar as it is empirically
variable, or leaves its possessors liable to partial and self-serving policies,
will not be enough. Only a universal birthright – and one strong enough
to deliver commands to the will – could withstand it. It is a pity then,
that Kerstein himself is not confident of a Kantian story of this kind, since
it seems to be the only hope for a theory of the requisite standing. Otherwise
there seems to be a straightforward empirical problem. If there is an inner
mechanism of reason strong enough to dragoon us all into the ranks of the
caring and just, it seems odd that so few of us get affected by it.
Why does Kerstein
suppose that on a sentimentalist story, the knaves and villains are exempt from
obligations? I should have thought no moral philosopher, except perhaps Gilbert
Harman, and certainly not Hume nor myself, could have been thought to suggest
such a thing. In fact, it seems to me such a shocking thing to say, that I am
at a loss to understand how Kerstein could have read Hume, or me, and perhaps
others such as Allan Gibbard, as saying anything that implies it. For the
record, I explicitly say the reverse, fairly often.[2]
The only
explanation I can offer for the misreading is that it comes from conflating two
different projects. One, the project of the anatomist, in HumeÕs terms, is to
give an accurate and complete account of the states of mind that gain
expression in moral thinking. The other, a moralistic project appropriate to
HumeÕs painter, is to give an account of the ÔsourcesÕ of our obligations. In
my discussion of Christine KorsgaardÕs account of Ôthe normative questionÕ I
voice some doubts about how to conduct this second project. Like other
pluralists, I think obligations arise for different reasons, and I am not
myself wedded to the idea that any one, clear, univocal concept, such as ÔutilityÕ
or Ôself-legislationÕ might have been thought to be, plays the same explanatory
role when we try to describe why we lie under one or another obligation. But it
is the anatomistÕs project that occupies the bulk of my work, and that
justifies calling me a ÔsentimentalistÕ.
If you confuse
these two projects, you might end up saying that moral obligations Ôstem fromÕ
or Ôare based inÕ psychological states, and thence infer that in the absence of
the psychological states, the obligations disappear as well. The anatomical
view is then supposed to lead to
bad morals or bad painting. But it is not I who says that. I would say, for
instance, that your obligations as a parent stem from the dependency of your
children, their needs, and the absence of other social resources provide a
substitute if you fail to meet those needs. One of these needs is affection, so
if you donÕt care about your child, you are in breach of the obligation that
the childÕs need places on you.[3]
The obligation does not come and go according to your affections, any more than
your debt comes and goes depending on whether you care about it. And I think it
shocking to suppose otherwise. The obligations you lie under, like the debts
you owe, donÕt decrease or disappear when you stop caring about them.
I think, then,
that parents of young children lie under a complex obligation, O. According to
the sentimentalist, I say this by way of expressing a complex of attitudes and
feelings towards the relationship between parents and their young children—what
I shall call Ôthese sentimentsÕ. Now let us say that someone who ignores or
negligently or deliberately falls short in fulfilling an obligation, fails O.
Finally, suppose we say that people who have no sentiments corresponding to
feeling the weight of an obligation, laugh-off O. Then all I ask is that we
recognize the distinction between:
If I (we) had not
had these sentiments, I (we) would not have been condemning parents who fail O
or even those who laugh-off O.
If I (we) had not
had these sentiments, I (we) would have failed O or laughed-off O.
If parents X do
not have these sentiments, then they are likely to fail O or laugh-off O
If parents X do
not have these sentiments, then they are under no obligation O.
The first three of
these are true and harmless. The last is false and deadly. But it is the last
that is foisted upon the sentimentalist in the passages I quoted.
I think the
transition from the harmless to the deadly is lubricated by careless use of
phrases like Ôis based uponÕ, or Ôstems fromÕ. If you ask me what moral thought
itself stems from or is based upon, then, as an anatomist, I give the
sentimentalist reply. If you ask me what a particular obligation or duty stems
from or is based upon, then my painterly answer may vary, but will seldom cite
the feelings of the agent. In this case it stems from the needs of the
children, and the sociological structures that makes the parent the person
responsible for meeting those needs. In the case of justice to outsiders, again
it may stem from the needs of the outsiders, or our overall needs for
accommodation with them, or perhaps it stems from fundamental rights to equal
treatment. I am not sure: the relationship between justice and mutual
advantage, and reciprocity, and equality, is obscure enough for me and many
others to feel insecure about exactly how best to paint it. What I am sure
about is that you cannot get rid of the obligations by not feeling them, or
laughing them off.
A trivial
misunderstanding becomes worrying when you find it shared by enough people. As
I have said, I fear that Kerstein is not alone. Christopher Peacocke has
recently suggested that sufficient attention to two-dimensional modal logic
conjures up a dependency claim which the quasi-realist must accept, but which
offends against some conviction that we hold.[4]
So, contrary to what I have repeatedly claimed, there is a mind-dependency
claim which causes trouble for any sentiment-oriented theory of value. The
technology in PeacockeÕs discussion will doubtless shock and awe enough readers
for it to be worth some trouble to show that it is in fact a smokescreen. The
issues can be put simply enough, and when they are, the objection disappears.
In a nutshell, the
issue goes like this. Peacocke
recognizes the general strategy I have repeatedly used. It is an
integral part of our ethical lives that we can evaluate scenarios that are
described to us, whether past, present, or merely possible or fictional. So if
you bring me a story about people and their doings, I can train my thoughts on
it, and according to the attitudes it elicits, I will admire it or condemn it,
or hold a whole variety of more or less nuanced responses. If you tell me a
story in which people fail to meet their childrensÕ needs, I react badly, and I
express the conviction that what they are doing is cruel and wrong. I hope we
all do. If asked why I condemn their behaviour, at least a prime part of my
answer is about the needs that are not being met. Perhaps this simplifies a little,
since the indifference of the perpetrators also matters, and that is a feature
of the perpetrator rather than of the children. But for clarity, and as a
harmless simplification, I shall say the verdict is child-dependent. If you
told me a story about people causing pain to animals such as dogs, my verdict
would be dog-dependent.
So far so good.
Now suppose your story is more complicated. You tell me a story in which people
not only ignore their childrensÕ needs, but also fail to condemn such behaviour, or even admire it.
They congratulate and esteem especially harsh or negligent parents. Their moral
sensibilities are here the opposite from ours. What am I to say about this? It
looks equally bad or somewhat worse to me. In the first story we could imagine
some guilt attaching to the behaviour: perhaps it is mainly adolescents or
criminals or failures who are bad with children, and their ordinary morality
condemns it. But in the second story, there is no condemnation from the people
who are described. They admire negligence or brutality. It is a horrible
scenario, and I deplore it the more.
I have often
stressed two further related points. The first is that someone could disagree with me about what I have just
said. He could urge that the fact that they find it admirable makes all the
difference, makes it admirable in fact. We have a moral disagreement, for I
deny that. I hold that it is the sad life of a child that is so shocking, and
in this imagined society, the parentsÕ self-congratulation at what they are
doing takes none of that away, but actually adds to it, making it even more
shocking. The second addition is that there might be examples—call them
etiquette examples—where the structure looks similar, but my opponent
would be right. For there are cases where the bad we do would not be bad at all
were it not for the communityÕs unfavourable take on it. I can imagine
communities (perhaps there are some) where it is very bad form indeed to give a
gift in return for a gift received. In such a community it would be insulting
and wrong to do something which amongst us would be a normal expression of
gratitude or reciprocated friendship, and it would be right to do
something—omitting to reciprocate— which amongst us would be a
breach of manners, and even insulting and wrong. In such a case it is true that
had we had these different attitudes, different actions would have been right
or wrong.[5]
Their value is due to the conventions of etiquette that people follow, and
these might have been harmlessly different. In the child case that is not so;
as I said, it is due to the unmet needs of the child.
How does Peacocke
hope to embarrass this analysis? He says some curious things about it. He says
at the beginning of the discussion
Ôit is very hard to see how it can be denied that, under (my) approach,
the conditions under which someone is correct in asserting a moral proposition
have something to do with expressed mental statesÕ [6]
And the intention is to show that although, as he recognizes, I claim not to
have a Ômind-dependentÕ treatment of morality, in fact I do. Unfortunately
these wordings, like KersteinÕs above, and others to which we shall come, are
ambiguous. Obviously an expressivist treatment of ethics is Ômind-dependentÕ in
one sense—it starts from reflections on the kind of mental state that
gets expressed when values are made public and exchanged. Obviously as well
Ôthe conditions under which someone is correct in asserting a moral proposition
have something to do with expressed mental statesÕ in one sense. Were the
expressed mental states different, the proposition would be different and would
be correct under different circumstances. For example, if the sentence Ôkicking
dogs is wrongÕ standardly expressed approval of kicking dogs, anyone voicing it
would be correct only in quite different circumstances, such as ones in which
dogs have no conscious states. But there is nothing worrying to the
expressivist (or anyone else) in thoughts such as those. The conditions under
which someone is correct in asserting any proposition has something to do with expressed mental
states, in this sense. It has to do with which beliefs are being expressed. Of
course, in another sense it has nothing to do with mental states: unless a
proposition is explicitly about the mind, its truth condition will be
world-dependent rather than mind-dependent. But similarly the truth (for I say
it is a truth) that you have an obligation to your children is child-dependent,
and the truth that you should not kick friendly dogs for fun is dog-dependent.
Peacocke pursues his attack via an indexing of
propositions, corresponding to reference first to the ÔworldÕ from which an
evaluation is made, and secondly to the ÔworldÕ that is being evaluated. To
this end he introduces the double index P(w1, w2),
explained as:
Proposition P,
when evaluated from the standpoint of psychological states in w1,
holds with respect to w2. [7]
P here is some
moral proposition, such as Ôit is wrong to kick dogs for funÕ or Ôthe
infliction of avoidable pain is wrongÕ. The overall proposition P(w1,
w2) is, however, not entirely clear, because of the curious and
treacherous word ÔholdsÕ (with its shades of Ôbased onÕ and Ôstems fromÕ).
Suppose someone says that the proposition that the war in Iraq was justified
holds from George BushÕs point of view. I can hear that as a contorted way of
saying that George Bush believes that the war in Iraq was justified, and it is
probably true. What I should not do is hear it as some kind of insinuation that
the war in Iraq was justified. ItÕs a description of what George Bush thinks,
not an endorsement of the way he thinks. Only a confused relativist of some
sophomoric stamp would accept the transition from Ôthe war in Iraq is justified
from George BushÕs point of viewÕ to Ôthe war in Iraq is justifiedÕ.
With that clear
for the moment, we can turn to the Ôw2Õ variable. For that to do any
work, there has to be some space between the proposition P and the variety of
worlds to which it applies, or in which it is evaluated. And this may be granted.
Ôit is wrong to kick dogs for funÕ can be tested against this world, or, if we
are imaginative enough, against slightly different worlds, for instance in
which there are still dogs and people, but only dogs that are unconscious, or
in which there are only people who can survive by nutrition from the pain of
other animals. And then it may turn out that the moral proposition is only true
contingently on aspects of our world, and would get a different truth value
were these other things different. Or of course, it may not. We may suppose
that however worlds vary, it is always wrong to cause unnecessary pain,
although even that may wobble if we bring in, for instance, apparently possible
people who like pain.
With these
explanations we can agree with Peacocke when he says that nobody can object to
the employment of this doubly indexed proposition. Nobody can object to it, for
P(w1, w2) can be the form of good enough propositions,
that can be regarded as true or as false in various cases, although they will often
be indeterminate, when we have not given definite enough interpretations of the
variables. Given what I have said, the evaluation of such propositions goes
like this. We tell what we might call a treble story. First we introduce a moral proposition P.
Second, we introduce some possible people with attitudes. And third we present
a possible scenario, and we imagine the people we just introduced evaluating
what goes on in the scenario, in accordance with the attitudes we gave them. If
the people introduced evaluate the introduced scenario in the way that would
properly gain expression by P, then P (w1, w2) should be
accorded T, otherwise not. It corresponds to Ôthe people we have introduced
evaluate the scenario we imagined them to be contemplating, in a way that could
be expressed by saying that PÕ. More concisely, we can say that the people we
have introduced evaluate the scenario we imagine them to be contemplating, in
the P-way.
Not surprisingly,
we can vary the people or psychological states introduced, and we can vary the
scenarios we conjure for them to be contemplating. So P(wi, wj)
can vary in two dimensions: there are two variables to be given interpretations
before we turn it into a definite claim. And filling in one does not determine
how we fill in the other. Or, of course we could quantify. ("wi)P(wi,
x) would mean that everyone from any possible story evaluates some given
scenario x in the P-way, and ("wj)P(z, wj) would
mean that the introduced persons with the psychological states z, evaluate
every possible scenario in the P-way. ("wi) ("wj)P(wi, wj)
would mean that everyone, whatever their other differences evaluates everything
in the P-way.
This is the
machinery, so what happens when it is set in motion? Alas, nothing at all. We
get a variety of rather cumbersome descriptions of what different people think
about different scenarios, and whether they would express themselves as
agreeing with some moral or ethical proposition. We get things like Ôwe, as we
are, think that in the world, as it is, kicking dogs is wrongÕ (true, I hope).
Or, Ôwe, as we would be were we to become coarse and callous, would think that
in the world as it is, kicking dogs is wrongÕ (false, no doubt). We can keep
the people constant (ÔusÕ) giving what Peacocke calls the ÔverticalÕ reading,
or we can vary people and scenarios together, giving what he calls a ÔdiagonalÕ
reading, such as the true Ôwe, as we would be were we to become coarse and
callous, would think that in a possible world in which dogs feel pain slightly
less than they do, kicking dogs is OKÕ.
Peacocke claims
that since there is this diagonal reading, there is a Ômind dependencyÕ claim
that the quasi-realist has not acknowledged. But that is just not true. Propositions
such as this last one amount to descriptions of how
people of some particular attitude (which we may or may not share) react to
different scenarios. And there is nothing in general in these descriptions to
offend the quasi-realist (or anyone else). It does not amount to giving our own
verdict on those same scenarios, although if make ourselves the topic, and
describe ourselves rightly, there will be the coincidence that what we say
about ourselves will be true just if we do assent to the verdict P.
The locutions that
Peacocke uses reveal him to be in the same swamp as Kerstein:
on the quasi
realistÕs theory the acceptability of basic moral principles depends on some
psychological attitudes. However this dependence is formulated, it must be possible
in thought to consider which propositions are correct when we vary the
standpoint of evaluation; that is, when we vary the first parameterÉ[8]
The first sentence
is again ambiguous. On the quasi-realistÕs theory the question of which basic
moral principles are accepted by people indeed depends upon (is the same thing
as) their psychological attitudes. Whether they are right to accept those
principles is a different thing altogether, and we will only settle it by
ourselves finding a verdict on their approvals and disapprovals. If people in
outer modal space, or for that matter people in benighted corners of the earth,
accept the principle that it is OK to cause unnecessary pain to sentient
creatures for fun, then they are cruel and callous and it would be good if they
would change. The second of PeacockeÕs quoted sentences is therefore
technically correct but highly misleading, for it implies that in general
changing the first parameter, that is, iconsidering different evaluative
standpoints, changes the correctness of a verdict. But it doesnÕt. It only changes whether
it is supposed to be
correct, by whichever evaluators are introduced. Except in the cases that I
called those of etiquette, it merely brings the evaluators into the embrace of
our verdict, perhaps to their discredit, as in this case.
Peacocke
continues:
Take a specific
moral principle identified by its content, say ÔPrima facie, the infliction of
avoidable pain is wrong (w,w). It seems to me that the quasi-realist, like
other mind-dependent theorists, must say this is false. It is false at those
entries in the diagonal for worlds in which we have different attitudes to the
infliction of avoidable pain
This is hard to
follow, because in accordance with his own explanation of the notation,
propositions of the form P(w1, w2), are not moral
principles at all. First, they describe whether the evaluation from w1,
of the scenario of w2, could gain expression by P: they are
descriptions, not evaluations. And secondly, they are not propositions at all
until the variables are bound or replaced by actual values, so neither the
quasi-realist nor anyone else has any business saying that P(w,w) is true, or
false.
Perhaps
Peacocke is thinking of the double
universal quantification ÔEveryone, from whatever evaluative standpoint, and
considering any scenario whatever, would agree that inflicting avoidable pain
is wrongÕ I do indeed doubt whether this is true, but that doubt has nothing to
do with quasi-realism. It has more to do with pessimism about varieties of the
wicked human heart, and if we are in outer modal space, the even more wicked
Martian heart. And after all, Peacocke shares the doubt, for he allows worlds
in which inhabitants have different attitudes to the infliction of pain. ThatÕs
the point on the diagonal that he is inviting to the feast. Or perhaps it is
not a double quantification but an anaphoric reference back to the world of the
people with the evaluative standpoint: Ôeveryone, from whatever evaluative
standpoint, and considering the world they inhabit, would agree that inflicting
avoidable pain is wrongÕ. Alas, the same pessimism is appropriate.
PeacockeÕs ambition is clearly to get the
quasi-realist both to
treat some proposition of the form P(w1, w2) as a genuine
moral principle, and to
evaluate it as false when we think of worlds in which the wicked hearts rule.
But the machinery takes him not one inch nearer to that goal. Worlds in which
the wicked hearts rule are still worlds in which, prima facie, the infliction
of avoidable pain is wrong. The wicked hearts may not agree with this, but then
that is just whatÕs wrong with them.
I
said that the word ÔholdsÕ, as it occurs in the clarification of his notation,
is treacherous, and at this point we are compelled to think that Peacocke has
actually been betrayed by it. It seems he really does want to index the
question of whether a moral principle is true to the various worlds whose
inhabitants either agree or disagree with it. I think that is preposterous. It
would be like saying that the proposition that the Iraq war was a good thing
holds—really holds—in Republican circles in America, and really
does not hold in most of the UK. And if that is what it means the quasi-realist
simply refuses to adopt the notation. It differs from the legitimate meaning we
have so far allowed it, aiming at something more like this: Ôthe people we have
introduced evaluate the scenario we imagined them to be contemplating, in a way
that could be expressed by saying that P and as a result P is trueÕ But the quasi-realist has no use for this
dogÕs breakfast of an assertion (it will be false except in etiquette cases).
The Iraq war was a bad thing whatever other people think about it. It is not
true in London but false in Texas. Nor is it a matter of etiquette, so that
enough thinking it a good thing might make it one. That way lies sophomoric
relativism, not sentimentalism. The criminality of the Iraq War is
dead-innocent-Iraqui-dependent, not Republican-sentiment-dependent.
Far from taking
him into the sunny uplands of rationalism, then, PeacockeÕs machinery grinds to
a halt in the swamp of a relativism of his own devising. He finishes the
discussion by considering the neighbouring case of colour, and the possibility
that creatures with different perceptual systems might see physically different
things and surfaces as red. He says that it is widely agreed that things would
not stop being red if humans lost their colour vision and saw only in shades of
grey. That may be so, although it ought also to be widely agreed that there is
much more indeterminacy here than in the case of values. Jonathan BennettÕs
example of phenol-thio-urea, which tastes bitter to some people and bland to
others, led many people to think that if the former group breeds into a huge
majority, the world becomes one in which the stuff is bitter, while if the
latter group does, the world becomes one in which it is bland. In other words,
the Ôresponse-dependencyÕ of secondary properties is a much better candidate
for providing a genuine truth condition for ascriptions of them, than any
similar attempt to provide a Ôtruth-conditionÕ for ascriptions of value.
However,
Peacocke is also correct that two-dimensionalism allows different formulations
of the idea that colours are mind-dependent. Where Q is some underlying
physical power, such as a disposition to reflect light of a certain wavelength
more than other light, and we imagine varying perceptual systems, we could say
that:
For any world,
whatever perceptual systems its inhabitants have, Q objects are red, as they
would be judged by us, as we actually are.
We would also want
to say:
In some worlds, Q
objects are not red, as judged by the inhabitants of those worlds.
And given
BennettÕs case, we might remain ambivalent about whether
For any world,
whatever perceptual systems its inhabitants have, Q objects are red.
Since we would be
ambivalent about, as it were, sticking with our own judgements, or entering
into the world-view of the people with the other perceptual system.
The
reason this ambivalence is harmless is that once we bring other perceptual
systems into view, the provided they are equally discriminatory, we lose any
very robust attachment to the idea that ours is right and theirs is wrong. Similarly we do not maintain sceptical
fears that perhaps our sense of smell, or sense of colour, may in general be
letting us down, so that perhaps things really smell differently from the way
we smell them, or have different hues from those we see them as having. People
who taste phenol-thio-urea the other way are not wrong, just different. But
there is no reason to suppose that this ambivalence extends similarly to the
case of value. [9] People who
are coarse and brutal are not ÔjustÕ different. They are also depraved, and as
a result they are rotten judges of value. If we are invited to Ôsee the world
as they see itÕ we can, perhaps, manage it, but we ourselves can attach no
weight to the verdicts we would imagine giving as we do so.
Before
leaving this part of the discussion, it may be useful to reflect upon a
difference between sentimentalism, as a theory of the origin of the moral
sentiments, and a partly parallel exercise of quasi-realism, attempting to see
our verdicts of modal necessity as the upshot of various features of the shape
of our minds that determine what we can or cannot imagine.[10]
Here there is a legitimate pressure to see a contingent source of imaginative
limitation as an undermining or debunking account of logical or metaphysical
necessity. If Ôwe cannot think otherwiseÕ is sourced in contingent facts about
us, an inference to Ôthings could not be otherwiseÕ is compromised rather than
explained.
Someone
might be tempted to use the modal case as a Trojan horse, bringing the same
worry into the theory of morals. But if so they would be wrong. The asymmetry
lies in what we say about the states of mind in question and how it relates to
the kinds of verdict we are making. In the modal case, if we find that the
modes of thought, or the absence of alternatives, are only contingent, their
source as an explanation of real necessity is compromised. But in the moral
case, it would be not finding that they are metaphysically contingent that would give them a parallel
debunking power. The parallel would be finding that they are morally indifferent. If it were morally alright to
have the other sentiments—say, approving of cruelty to dogs or neglect of
children—then it would be hard to believe that the ones we actually have
could source a robust confidence in an obligation to refrain from cruelty and
neglect. At least in general, if it is OK to think that some action is OK, then
the action is OK.
But the
sentimentalist is not saying that it is OK to have the contrary sentiments. As
I have already said, the sentiments of those who would think otherwise fall
within the scope of proper disapproval. We do not just disapprove of neglect of
children, but perhaps even more so, and certainly just as much, we disapprove
of those who approve of it or even tolerate it.
And rationalists
had better not find the metaphysical contingency of modes of moral thought
unsettling. If rationalist moral conviction is to falter whenever it comes upon
people who do not share it or do not feel its force, then it is a fragile thing
indeed. For knavery exists. Indeed, it often rules, and this is why a robust
conviction of its baseness is so important.
Kerstein is not
the first to worry about the scope of justice on HumeÕs theory. According to
Manfred KuehnÕs biography, Kant himself was led to reject HutchesonÕs
sentimentalism for a very similar reason.[11]
Reading Rousseau apparently convinced Kant that while the sentimentalist allows
that we have duties of charity to the dispossessed of the world, this is not
enough. The poor or excluded have a right to more than charity. It is not
charity they want or need, but justice. If sentimentalism cannot deliver that,
then it delivers an inadequate account of the actual nature of our moral
thought.
Hume
makes himself a target for this kind of outraged reaction:
Were there a
species of creatures intermingled with men, which, though rational, were
possessed of such inferior strength, both of body and mind, that they were
incapable of all resistance, and could never, upon the highest provocation,
make us feel the effects of their resentment; the necessary consequence, I
think, is that we should be bound by the laws of humanity to give gentle usage
to these creatures, but should not, properly speaking, lie under any restraint
of justice with regard to them, nor could they possess any right or property,
exclusive of such arbitrary lords.
Our intercourse with them could not be called society, which supposes a
degree of equality; but absolute command on the one side, and servile obedience
on the other. Whatever we covet,
they must instantly resign: Our
permission is the only tenure, by which they hold their possessions: Our compassion and kindness the only
check, by which they curb our lawless will: And as no inconvenience ever results from the exercise of
power, so firmly established in nature, the restraints of justice and property,
being totally useless,
would never have place in so unequal a confederacy. (190-191)
There are many
things to say about this passage, and quite how Hume thought it related to the
human cases he goes on to discuss, which are firstly European relationships to
indigenous American people, and secondly mensÕ relationships with women. The
clear implication is that the model applies in neither case, but only at best
to our relationship with animals, or perhaps imagined animals.
Nevertheless we
might want to modify the account to make justice clearly applicable, even in
the circumstances of the thought experiment. I shall consider how that might be
done in a moment. Meanwhile, the important point is that it is not HumeÕs
sentimentalism that leads him here, but his strict delineation of the
circumstances of justice and its source in mutual advantage. Hume does not deny
that we have obligations
to the creatures he presents. He says that we are Ôbound by the laws of
humanityÕ to give them gentle usage. The only issue is the way we are to
understand this obligation. Remembering that for Hume the virtue of justice is
both Ôcautious and jealousÕ and above all artificial, it may not be so bad for
these creatures if the source of that obligation lies elsewhere. But it is
important to see that if we insist on the word ÔjusticeÕ, the sentimentalist
can give it to us.
Hume mentions the
resentment these creatures have, but which, because of their inferior strength
and power, they can do nothing to visit upon us. This opens up a new
sentimentalist vista, much more thoroughly explored by Adam Smith.[12]
As Raphael explains, for Smith the sympathy that lies at the bottom of our
capacity for morals has a slightly different shape than it does in Hume.[13]
In Hume, we sympathize with the pleasure or pain that an action gives to a
person. In Smith, we sympathize with different states of mind, including the
motives of an agent, and more relevantly to the current case, with the
gratitude or resentment of those affected by the action. Indeed our sense of
justice, for Smith, is dependent on reactions of resentment or gratitude to
actions, which need not vary as the actual quantity of harm or benefit they
bring about.
The ÔsympathyÕ
that is so prominent in each of Hume and Smith is translated, by the one into
respect for the general point of view, and by the other into the voice of the impartial
spectator, the Ôman within the breastÕ who represents the reactions of those
without. There is, of course, much to be said about the ways in which each
writer identifies and handles the mechanism, and the relation between them.[14]
There is also much to be said about whether either mechanism implies some
concession to rationalism, bringing in as they do some notion of ÔcorrectedÕ
sentiments. I cannot rehearse all that needs saying about that here, but shall
have to take it as given that neither writer betrays sentimentalism by their
construction of the more complex sensitivity.[15]
So suppose we bring in the lynchpin of SmithÕs sentimentalism, the Ôreal,
revered, and impartial spectatorÕ whose function is to bring home to us the
resentment of those affected by our delinquencies. When the voice of this
spectator is heard as it should be, we may recoil from our own contemplated or
actual conduct. In HumeÕs terms, we can no longer bear our own survey.
Recognizing this resentment of our conduct, and feeling no defence against it,
we admit the injustice.
Suppose, then,
that we have been minded to take from one of HumeÕs creatures something which
they evidently cherish. They cannot visit their resentment upon us, but somehow
we know that they feel it, and we know that we would feel it in their shoes.
The man within the breast voices this resentment on their behalf, and we find
we cannot dismiss it (we cannot resent their resentment, as we sometimes can).
This unpleasant impact is the same as guilty awareness of the injustice of our
conduct. What more could the sternest moralist ask from us?
SmithÕs
modification of Hume may still leave us falling short of full-blown Kantian
rationalism. But it is at least telling that the most fervent contemporary
Kantians find it hard to do better. Korsgaard, for instance gives us the
crucial moment in the genesis of obligation to others like this:
How does this
obligation come about? Just the
way that Nagel says that it does.
I invite you to consider how you would like it if someone did that to
you. You realize that you would
not merely dislike it, you would resent it. You would think that the other has a reason to stop - more,
an obligation to stop. And that
obligation would spring from your own objection to what he does to you.[16]
Korsgaard goes on
to employ a cognitive or rationalistic vocabulary, but it is hard not to feel
that the central process is exactly the same as in Smith. The potential victim
forces you to recognize his resentment, and to Ôput yourself in his shoesÕ. His
fundamental question is: how would you like it if someone did that to youÕ — and once you
find that you would not, then, other things being equal, his not liking or
resenting it translates into your own discomfort at your own behaviour. Of
course, as Smith sensibly recognizes, things are not always equal. We have an
abundance of defence mechanisms against this incipient discomfort, including
ignoring the impartial spectator, or more often convincing ourselves the he
would be on our side or Ôof our factionÕ.[17]
At
this point the sentimentalist will certainly face another familiar challenge.
The account finds the source of feelings of obligation and injustice in a
certain emotional identification: in this case a contingent (of course)
capacity to internalize the resentments of others. But might not this very
notion of resentment itself import, and depend upon, an unacknowledged
cognitivism? Resentment, as Korsgaard says, is more than mere dislike. Perhaps
it is more like bitterness, but bitterness at the dispensation of some agent.
Anyone suffering a third summer holiday in succession blighted by continuous
rain might feel bitter, but only a theist can resent it. This quickly suggests
that resentment is more like bitterness at the injustice of the behaviour, in
which case a perception of injustice cannot be explained in terms of resentment
and sympathy with it, but must be identified in some pre-existent cognition.
Similar objections may be made to sentimentalist uses of notions like guilt, or
even anger: if anger is the attitude or emotion of those who perceive
themselves to have been wronged, and guilt is the attitude or emotion of those
who recognize themselves to have done wrong, then we cannot understand the
judgments by citing the emotions.
There
is a simple lacuna in this popular line of thought. The equations in question
are things like Ôanger is perception of wrongÕ or Ôresentment is recognition of
injustice to oneselfÕ. The objection implicitly supposes that these equations
need to be read from right to left, so that the apparent cognition explains the
emotion. The sentimentalist tradition, by contrast, reads them from left to
right, so that the emotion or attitude explains the thought of wrong or
injustice in terms of which it gets expressed. This is not the place to
rehearse all the moves in this debate. You just have to try out the different
directions of explanation, and you have to ask which is psychologically or
metaphysically the more economical. But at least a preliminary remark is that
as they stand, of course, the equations are absurdly simple. Anger is not
perception of wrong, nor resentment recognition of injustice to oneself. Each
is both more in one respect and less in another. More, because the pure
cognition leaves out the upheaval and the motivational force, so that in fact
perception of wrong may not lead to anger, and recognition of injustice to
oneself may not lead to resentment. Less, because each has a primitive identity
in which ethical thought is not yet present. After all, we should not forget
that Darwin called his great work The Expression of Emotion in Man and
Animals. The guard dog
does a fair job of being angry at the intruder, and the pet which throws its
food around the house on being left behind, does a fair job of resenting being
neglected. [18]
A different strand
in Smith is the idea that unlike obligations of benevolence, obligations of
justice can be exacted from us. They bring in the potential force of the
community or the civil power: Ôthe person himself who meditates an injustice is
sensible of this, and feels that force may, with the utmost propriety, be made
use of both by the person whom he is about to injure, and by others, either to
obstruct the execution of his crime, or to punish him when he has executed it.Õ[19]
Applied to HumeÕs example, this suggests that the question of whether there is
an obligation of justice may hinge on whether we think a spectator,
contemplating a breach of Ôgentle usageÕ,
should use pre-emptive or retaliatory force on the perpetrator. I am not
sure whether we do think this in general. If we can take the case of animals as
indicative, our actual animal welfare legislation suggests we think that if the
breach is severe enough then the criminal law has a say, but at least in our
jurisprudence, if not in our studies, we seem prepared to let a fair amount of
not so gentle usage go on unprevented and unpunished.
However
we solve this issue, if we stand back for a moment it should be obvious that
this particular issue about justice is not a promising basis from which to
attack sentimentalism. The structure of the case disqualifies it from that
task. The idea is to arouse our sense of what is due to these creatures, and to
encourage shock and outrage at the base behaviour to which HumeÕs agents might
be led, or to excite us to lament the outrages which they might get away with,
and to wring our hands over the sad plight of the poor defenceless
creatures. All this is excellent.
It shows us sympathizing with the downtrodden and their resentment, perhaps
desiring or wishing for a civil order in which the powerful would be punished,
feeling that things are out of joint unless they are brought to account for
their crimes, and so on. In other words, it shows that our sense of outrage and
injustice is mobilized, not merely our benevolence. But it cannot show more
than that. It cannot show that what is mobilized lies outside the sentiments
altogether. HumeÕs example may make us hot under the collar about the
indignities the powerful may visit on the weak, but it does not afford any
evidence that getting hot under the collar is anything else than feeling an
attitude and emotion, directed upon a particular social structure and the
abuses it looks set to allow.
I have not, in
this paper, been exclusively defending expressivism. Other views which stress
the place of sentiments, or imagination and culture, in the genesis of our
ethical thought were equal possible targets of Kerstein and PeacockeÕs attacks.
Some of these others, perhaps less deft with the notion of Ômind dependenceÕ
might even fall to such attacks, for instance by giving the moral judgement a
truth-condition that is not child-dependent or dog-dependent, but genuinely
mind-dependent. Others may avoid them only by inappropriate reliance on
ÔactuallyÕ operators and other pieces of doubtful machinery. If so, I am glad
to part company with them.
The
popularity of rationalism, and the general feeling that there Ômust be
something toÕ the kinds of argument I have been discussing, are very
deep-rooted. Partly, they represent a noble dream. They answer a wish that the
knaves of the world can be not only confined and counfounded, but refuted
– refuted as well by standards that they have to acknowledge. Ideally,
the will be shown to be in a state akin to self-contradiction. Kerstein
acknowledges that Kant and neo-Kantians have not achieved anything like this
result. But it is still, tantalizingly there as a goal or ideal, the Holy Grail
of moral philosophy, and many suppose that all right-thinking people must join
the pilgrimage to find it.
We
sentimentalists do not like our good behaviour to be hostage to such a search.
We donÕt altogether approve of
Holy Grails. We do not see the need for them. We are not quite on all fours
with those who do. And we do not quite see why, even if by some secret alchemy
a philosopher managed to glimpse one, it should ameliorate his behaviour, let
alone that of other people. We think instead that human beings are ruled by
passions, and the best we can do it to educate them so that the best ones are
the most forceful ones.
We say of
rationalistic moral philosophy what Hume says of abstract reasonings in
general, that when we leave our closet, and engage in the common affairs of
life, its conclusions seem to vanish, like the phantoms of the night on the
appearance of the morning.[20]
[1] David Hume, An Enquiry Concerning the Principles of Morals, ed. Tom Beauchamp, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1998, Appendix I, p. 163.
[2] Ruling Passions, (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1998) p. 210, p. 230, p. 265, and elsewhere. And why does Kerstein think I call the foreign-office knave a knave?
[3] If you (wrongly) think that we cannot lie under an obligation to feel various ways, perhaps because ÔoughtÕ implies ÔcanÕ, read it as Ôbehaving as though you care for the childÕ.
[4] Christopher Peacocke, The Realm of Reason, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2004.
[5] One could play with complexities introduced by the thought that in some sense Ônot giving a gift backÕ in the described community is performing the same action as Ôgiving a gift backÕ in ours. They do not affect the point.
[6] Christopher Peacocke, The Realm of Reason, p. 208.
[7] p. 210.
[8] p. 214
[9] In her illuminating paper ÔHistory of Philosophy in Philosophy Today: and the Case of Secondary QualitiesÕ (Philosophical Review, 1992, pp. 191 – 226) Margaret Wilson comments on a constant tendency in Ôthe modern philosophyÕ to vacillate over whether colours are in the mind, are categorical or primary grounds in the atomic constitution of things and their surfaces, or are powers to excite human perceptual systems. The vacillation is more excusable if we reflect that in the case of colour we never have to decide on Ôwhat to sayÕ about the case when the same physical properties have different powers because of varying perceptual systems.
[10] Simon Blackburn ÔMorals and ModalsÕ in Essays in Quasi-Realism, New York: Oxford University Press, 1993.
[11] Manfred Kuehn, Kant, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2001.
[12] In the paragraphs that follow, on Smith, I am much indebted to work by Michael Ridge.
[13] Adam Smith, The Theory of Moral Sentiments, ed. D.D. Raphael and A.M. Macfie, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1976, editorÕs introduction, p. 13.
[14] See, for instance, Rachel Cohon, ÔThe Common Point of View in HumeÕs EthicsÕ, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, vol 57, 1997, Christine Korsgaard, ÔThe General Point of View: Love and Moral Approval in HumeÕs EthicsÕ, Hume Studies, vol 25, 1999, Elizabeth Radcliffe, ÔHume on Motivating Sentiments, the General Point of View, and the Inculcation of MoralityÕ Hume Studies, vol 20, 1994, Geoff Sayre-McCord. ÔOn Why Hume's 'General Point of View' isn't Ideal - and Shouldn't BeÕ Social Philosophy and Policy vol 11, 1994.
[15] In Ruling Passions I argue that the idea of the general point of view involves no such concession, but only introduces what I call a ÔHume-friendlyÕ notion of reason. See Chapters 7 and 8.
[16]Korsgaard, The Sources of Normativity, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1996, p. 98.
[17] Smith: ÔThe propriety of our moral sentiments is never so apt to be corrupted, as when the indulgent and partial spectator is at hand, while the indifferent and impartial one is at a great distanceÕ. p. 154.
[18] For more on these themes, see my ÔHow Emotional is the Virtuous Person?Õ in Peter Goldie, ed. Understanding Emotions: Mind and Morals, Aldershot: Ashgate Publishing, 2002.
[19] Smith, pp. 79-80.
[20] David Hume, A Treatise of Human Nature, Book III, part 1, section 1.