Umberto Eco: Kant and the Platypus: Essays on Language and Cognition, New York: Harcourt Brace and Company,
1999, 464pp. $28.00
I
The title gives due advertisement of EcoÕs trademarks: high themes,
arcane learning, strange corners of philosophy and history and natural history,
large intellectual vistas, above all a sense of play. Readers excited by these
prospects will probably already be familiar with The Name of the Rose or FoucaultÕs Pendulum. They should be warned that the
intellectual temperature is here supposed to be much higher, as Eco reverts to
his academic interest in semiotics, or the theory of signs and communication.
The book makes no concessions to the reader. It takes us into difficult
writers, such as Heidegger, Kant and Peirce, and into their worst parts. This
is entirely self-conscious, since Eco himself is reported as saying: ÔThis a
hard-core book. ItÕs not a page turner. You have to stay on every page for two
weeks with your pencil. In other words, donÕt buy it if you are not Einstein.Õ
(CBS, Sunday December 5th, 1999). Such braggadocio (Eco-terrorism,
perhaps) certainly fits the work, which is clearly that of a person in whom the
sense of doubt is less developed than other ambitions, such as cutting an
intellectual figure, or appearing as something of a priest or magus.
EcoÕs book resists classification, like the platypus
of the title. It is not a work of philosophy, nor of scholarship, nor cognitive
science, although it bears resemblances to such works. Unlike, say, Alice in
Wonderland, it is not an
entertainment either, although it is entertaining in some places, and often
tries to be so. Like the platypus, it comes across as a bit of this and a bit
of that. Its nature is indicated by the publisherÕs disclaimer: ÔForgoing a
formal, systematic treatment, Eco engages in a series of explorationsÉÕÑ
although this is also a little disingenuous. It gives the impression that a
formal systematic treatment of something is just around the corner, extant
even, but that Eco modestly hesitates to give it to us. In truth, however, it
is hard to imagine what has been forgone, just as it would be if someone said
the same thing about the Alice books. Eco is not one to concentrate on one thing at a time, which is
presumably a precondition of formal and systematic thought. He is a polymath
who likes to sidetrack us, and the topics tumble over one another and compete
for attention. I nearly said that we are watching the flight of the butterfly,
not the stoop of the hawk. But both creatures fly in the clear air, whereas
here we are in the swamps, and much of the time we are close to suffocation.
Sometimes you might manage a wry smile when you finally surface, but generally
speaking, EcoÕs warning not to buy the book is sound, whether or not you are
Einstein.
II
It is fair to start with the more positive side. This is the book of a
very clever man who has read enormously. The individual chapters or essays give
the impression of contributing to serious philosophical questions and problems.
Furthermore, when Eco does allow us to come up for air, we often find ourselves
pretty much on the side of the angels. He has noticed, for example, that it is
not true that anything goes. There is a real world that, even if it admits of
different descriptions or interpretations, nevertheless offers Ôlines of
resistanceÕ to false or inadequate thinking. If there is a boulder in your path
and you fail to perceive it, things go worse. They go worse in ways painfully
apt to show what is wrong with the idea that there is nothing beyond the text.
You know reality when you come up against it. Language, as Eco puts it, does
not create being ex nihilo
(p. 54). It is sad that this still needs to be said, and it is well worth
remembering that even the idealist Berkeley said it. Still, given that there
are parts of the academy where truth and reality are still endangered species,
it is good to find a large-scale intellectual like Eco getting this right.
Incidentally, EcoÕs notion of resistance pleasantly echoes the motto (ÔLes
choses sont contre nousÕ: things are against us) of the resistentialist school
of philosophers invented by the humorist Paul Jennings. In JenningsÕs parody,
the French derived this by remorseless logic (ÔFrom this it follows, or it does
in the FrenchÉÕ), whereas the empirical English established it by dropping
pieces of buttered toast on carpets, and finding that the toast fell buttered
side down with a frequency in direct proportion to the value of the carpet. Eco
thinks that resistance is a manifestation of Being, or, as one might say less
gravely, it is just one of those things.
Eco can also be good on constraints on
interpretationÑas one might again expect, given that FoucaultÕs Pendulum is a long allegory on the idiocies of
unconstrained frenzies of taking one thing as a sign of another. The problem
with that book is that the skepticism is muted. It requires of us a lot of
devotion to numerology, the cabala, the Protocols of the Elders of Zion, the
Knights of the Rosy Cross, and the rest of the menagerie before we are
permitted to dismiss them, and even then the permission is curiously
half-hearted. In the current book, Eco is more forthright, perhaps abjuring a
wilder youth. Indeed, philosophically the most interesting part of the book is
EcoÕs defense of rocks of genuine fixed meaning that stay put among the seas of
reinterpretation. He reports a debate with Richard Rorty, who had alluded to
the right we have to interpret a screwdriver as something useful to scratch our
ears with, and EcoÕs reply is surely exemplary:
A screwdriver can serve also to open a parcel (given
that it is an instrument with a cutting point, easy to use in order to exert
force on something resistant); but it is inadvisable to use it for rummaging
about in your ear precisely because it is sharp and too long to allow the hand
to control the action required for such a delicate operation; and so it would
be better to use not a screwdriver but a light stick with a wad of cotton at
its tip.
It may be hard to believe that Rorty had really got himself into a
state in which it would seem strange that a plumber carries tools different
from those of a doctor. But perhaps he had. As the philosopher J.L. Austin once
remarked, there is always the bit where you say it, and the bit where you take
it back.
Eco is deft on truth in fiction:
It has been said that narrative worlds are always little
worlds, because they do
not constitute a maximal and complete state of thingsÉIn this sense narrative
worlds are parasitical,
because, if the alternative properties are not specified, we take for granted
the properties that hold good in the real world. In Moby Dick it is not expressly stated that all the
sailors aboard the Pequod
have two legs, but the reader ought to take it as implicit, given that the
sailors are human beings. On the other hand the account takes care to inform us
that Ahab had only one leg, but, as far as I remember, it does not say which,
leaving us free to use our imagination, because such a specification has no
bearing on the story.
A final example of dexterity also introduces a reservation. Consider
the hoary old problem: ÔWhy do mirrors reverse left to right and not up to
down?Õ Eco talks of mirrors at length, and he gives a short but very confident
solution to the problem. This is itself unusual, since in general Eco cherishes
mysteries rather than solving them. Eco claims that mirrors do not reverse
anything at all. He invites us to think, not of a mirror, but of a Ôprosthetic
eyeÕ, a third eye situated in our index finger. If we point this at ourselves
we will obtain the view somebody has who is facing us, which, he seems to
think, is equally the view the mirror gives us. It is this point of view that
ÔreversesÕ left to right, but that just means that it is facing in the opposite
direction to our normal point of view. In a footnote Eco tweaks the
psychologist Richard Gregory:
Gregory also quotes GardnerÉwho had also made the
obvious observation that mirrors do not reverse anything at all. But not even
this is enough for Gregory, and he adds another reason for surprise: that
mirrors also reverse depth, and that is to say, if we walk away from a mirror,
say toward the north, the image moves away from us toward the south, and it
gets smaller (I would add that itÕs hardly likely to come running straight at
us). But, Gregory says, mirrors do not reverse concave and convex. All you have
to do is think of the mirror as a prosthesis, or an eye on the index finger,
and it will let me see what I would see if someone were standing in front of
me: if that someone moves away, his image gets smaller, but if he has a
potbelly, then it will stay that way, nor will the pit of his stomach contract
toward the inside.
Again, this is amusing. The playfulness works well. The problem is that
it begins to look a little uncritical when a momentÕs thought shows that if
this is EcoÕs theory, it is incorrect. The view in a mirror is not the view obtained by looking at someone
standing in front of you, nor is it the view obtained by an eye looking at you.
To see this, hold an ordinary book on your chest and look in a mirror. You will
have difficulty reading the writing. But to a person looking at you, the
writing reads normally, and of course if you now ask your partner to hold the
book outwards and face you, you have no difficulty reading it either.
Mirror-writing does not appear in either of these views. Incidentally, I say
Ôif this is EcoÕs theoryÕ deliberately, because here, as throughout, he shows a
gift for evasion, and it is extremely hard to be sure what he actually believes.
The quotations I have given strike me as pleasantly
humorous. But as Bernard Williams observed in a review of earlier works of
EcoÕs (New York Review of Books, 1995), his genuine wit is juxtaposed with things that seemed unfunny
to a bewildering degree. In the present work we could contrast the passages I
have just quoted with a long and labored exercise in which Eco draws a ÔmapÕÑin
fact, two mapsÑ of an imaginary town called ÔVanvilleÕ. The streets and
landmarks of this town are labeled with names and terms found as examples in
the writings of the philosopher Quine. The only intellectual point of the
exercise, which stretches over ten pages, is to show that it is difficult to
locate things by referring to landmarks once the landmarks have vanished. The
ulterior motive seems to be to display a cosy intimacy with QuineÕs writing,
and indeed with Quine personally (ÔVan is how Willard Van Orman Quine was known
to close friendsÕ). I do not know whether the claim is justified (and why the
past tense?), but the thing is excruciating either way.
III
Before we get to Kant or the platypus, the book begins with a chapter
on Being. Here is a fairly typical sample, from p. 30:
As Heidegger says in Being and Time (¤490), angst constitutes the opening of
being-there to its existence as being thrown for its own end; agreed, and the
(grammatical) subject of this thrown being is the Dasein. But then why is it said immediately
afterward that Òbecause of it [angst], being opens to being-thereÓ and the
Òbeing of being-there is totally at stakeÓ? The being of being-there is pure
tautology. Being-there cannot be based on something, given that it is ÒthrownÓ
(why? because it is).
Whence comes this das Sein that opens itself to being-there, if the being-there that opens itself
is an entity among the entities?
Whence indeed. Now, it would be wrong to ridicule this before
explanation, for philosophers must be allowed their bits of terminology. It is
much better to ridicule it afterwards. So: to say that something opens to
being-there means that people think about it. Angst we all know about: fear of death and
absurdity and all that. Something is said to be thrown at us if we canÕt do
anything about it, although admittedly that does not explain why our existence
is thrown Ôfor its own endÕ, whatever that may mean. If we want to know what
Being is, we will have plenty to look back upon. ÔHere is what we mean by the
word Being: SomethingÕ
(p. 12). On the other hand ÔBeing is the horizon, or the amniotic fluid, in
which our thought naturally movesÕ (p. 17). I donÕt know if I live an unusually
cluttered life, but I find it difficult to reconcile these two statements.
Something bumped into my car last week, but I donÕt believe it was either a
horizon or an amniotic fluid (all right, we are not supposed to take it
literallyÑbut then we must ask ourselves if we know how to take it).
Anyhow, ÔBeing is even before it
is talked aboutÕ. Being also pops up in Latin: ÔBeing is id quod primum
intellectus concipit quasi notissimumÕ (p. 19). We have also been told the answer to the
question, ÔWhy is there being rather than nothing?Õ The answer, adverted to
above, is: ÔBecause there isÕ (p. 17, EcoÕs italics). This answer, which Eco insists must be taken
Ôwith the maximum seriousnessÕ, is nevertheless in danger of being retired two
pages later when we are equally told that Ôthere is no need to wonder why there
is being; it is a luminous evidenceÕ.
All this may help the reader understand the quoted
paragraph, or there again it may not. P. G. Wodehouse talks of family occasions
best avoided, when Aunt is calling to Aunt like mastodons bellowing across
primeval swamps, and EcoÕs sparring with Heidegger reminds me of them. In fact,
insofar as we can keep score here, it seems to go like this. Heidegger holds
that it is only because people are afraid of death that they become
self-conscious, or perhaps conscious of the world around them. This is
analogous to the StoicsÕ view that it is only because people are afraid of
death that they seek political office and want to have statues erected to
themselves. These are not very convincing ideas, but if this is HeideggerÕs
stumbling at a thought, then EcoÕs reply that consciousness is ÔthrownÕ, or
even Ôpure tautologyÕ, is clearly off-target. Consciousness and
self-consciousness are worth explaining, and in principle at least an emotion
like fear of death might be part of the explanation, unlikely though it sounds.
What has gone wrong? Meditation upon Being has roots
in Parmenides, Plato, Plotinus, Anselm, or Aquinas, and need not be
disreputable. What is disreputable is the way these meditations become hijacked
by oracular obscurity, in which Eco collaborates with Heidegger, who at least
had the excuse of being a theologian by training. It might seem merely tiresome
when intellectuals trick out some banal thoughts (Nature turns up people who
think; Sometimes they get worried; They think about death; The modern world is
horrid) in terms of Being, Being-there, Being revealing itself, angst, and the rest. But in fact it matters a
great deal, as the famous double dactyl reminds us:
Higgledy piggledy
Herr Rektor Heidegger
Said to his students:
ÒTo Being Be True!Ó
ÒLest you should fall into
Inauthenticity.
This I believeÑ
And the FŸhrer does too!Ó
In other words, lament that we have lost the shelter of Being, and soon
you start wanting a recipe for recovering it. Clearly this requires
authenticity, best discovered through nineteenth-century Romantic visions of
inarticulate ancient purity, the Fatherland, blood, and destiny. You then find
that the quest requires a political expression, such as, for instance, the Nazi
party, whose unique rapport with primordial Being was so striking to Heidegger,
just as that of the Prussian state had been to Hegel. The sleep of reason
produces monsters, or as Voltaire said, those who can make you believe
absurdities can make you commit atrocities.
Eco is not dangerous enough to produce monsters, and
his interest is not really in ontology or cosmology. The bouts with Heidegger
come across as mere rites of passage, certificates of profundity. His real
interest is in the nature of signs and cognition.
IV
If there is a single central theme in this work, it is the problem of
universals, or of the relation between particular things and general
categories. Eco introduces this topic by means of cases where we come across
things that stretch previous classifications. When Marco Polo arrived in Java,
he came across the rhinoceros and was only able to regard it as a rather
scrubby unicorn. When Spanish cavalry arrived in the New World, MontezumaÕs
subjects did not know what they were seeing, or even whether they were looking
at one animal or two.
Kant never came across the platypus, unless possibly
by hearsay towards the very end of his life. But Eco finds interesting the
question of how Kant might have reacted to a beast that resisted familiar
biological categories. I am not sure why this is an interesting question: Kant,
like anybody else, would be faced with the problem of warping his scientific
heritage to fit the new experience. It is not clear that the critical
philosophy gives him any special understanding of this process, or any reason
to conduct it in some special way. In fact, as Eco admits, the question is
speculative, for Kant does not tell us much about small-scale, everyday
empirical concepts, like those of a dog or a chair or a platypus. He is happier
with highly abstract concepts, like those of substance or time, or space or
causation, and even a platypus is a thing that lasts for a time, occupies
space, resists penetration, and is subject to gravity.
Still, Eco wants to link Kant to the platypus. So he
directs us to one chapter of the Critique of Pure Reason where Kant seems to address the way in
which concepts become applicable in experience. Even here it is not really
clear that Kant intends to be talking about everyday empirical concepts. KantÕs
chapter is entitled ÔThe Schematism of the Pure Concepts of UnderstandingÕ,
which certainly suggests otherwise, since the pure concepts of understanding
are the big abstract categories. In any case, the chapter was a notorious
show-stopper even in KantÕs own time. Jacobi called it Ôthe most wonderful and
most mysterious of all unfathomable mysteries and wondersÕ. Many modern
commentators have dismissed it out of hand. Their view is that Kant had set
himself an unanswerable question, along the lines of, ÔWhat is the rule for
applying rules to experience?Õ or, ÔWhat is the recipe for making use of
recipes?Õ The complaint is that there cannot be a rule for applying rules in
general. Any answer would be regressive, having to consist in producing another
rule or recipe, about which the same question would then, inevitably, be
asked.
This
moral is often credited to Wittgenstein, who is indeed adept at uncovering
hidden regresses in various accounts of our understanding. For example, we are
apt to feel that spontaneous judgements might be explained by our having, in
our mindÕs eye, diagrams or templates or little pictures telling us what we are
looking at. So if I am told to pick a red flower, perhaps I do so by conjuring
up my red picture, and picking a flower that bears a sufficient resemblance to
the picture. WittgensteinÕs comment on this in The Blue Book is lethalÑone of the best short refutations
in philosophy:
But this is not the only way of searching and it isnÕt
the usual way. We go, look about us, walk up to a flower and pick it, without
comparing it to anything. To see that the process of obeying the order can be
of this kind, consider the order Òimagine a red patchÓ. You are not tempted in this case to
think that before obeying you must have imagined a red patch to serve you as a
pattern for the red patch which you were ordered to imagine.
Wittgenstein points out that there has to be a stop to producing
interpretations of words (or diagrams or images). There has to be a point at
which we just go ahead and do what we were told, without consulting any mental diagrams or templates
or words at all.
But this is also a point that Kant himself makes,
immediately before the chapter on schematism. So charity seems to require that
we find something for Kant to be doing other than committing mistakes against
which he has just warned us. The best suggestion, I believe, takes seriously
his own warning that he is talking about Ôan art concealed in the depths of the
human soul, whose real modes of activity nature is hardly likely ever to allow
us to discover, and to have open to our gazeÕ. The art is the art of judgment,
and the reason that it is concealed in the depths of the soul is precisely that
it cannot be reduced to the grasp of rules, or recipes, or criteria. Nor can it
be reduced to the presence, before the mind, of a thing like a picture or a
even a word, and for WittgensteinÕs reason. Even when pictures, diagrams, and
words float before our
mindÕs eye, judgment only comes about when we have taken them the right
way. Judgment then requires something spontaneous, outside the domain of
reason; yet this ÒsomethingÓ is a precondition for making any application of
reason.
This can all sound very mysterious. We are not
comfortable with arts concealed in the depths of the soul. But what we are
facing is bedrock, the unthinking deployment of customs and routines that make
up the way in which we are usually at home in the world. When it comes to
recognizing things, we just do it. Common sense and philosophical reflection
can tell us no more. There can indeed be a further science of the functions of
the brain that enable us to just do it, and of course there exist remarkable
data on what happens when those functions are damaged. But Eco is explicit that
he intends to offer no contribution to any such science.
So what is he doing? He talks at length of the
particular and the general, and the nature of symbolization, yet it is never
clear that he has grasped WittgensteinÕs point, or KantÕs. He reverts
constantly to the idea of us applying a diagram, or icon, or schema as if this
is the essential but mysterious element in explaining the process of judgement.
Perhaps semiotics is an open invitation to this idea. Semiotics is the study of
what occurs when one thing is a sign of another. To suppose that it is
fundamental to cognition is, then, to suppose that cognition is essentially a
matter of comparing one thing with another; and this is precisely the model
that Wittgenstein and Kant oppose.
V
Where it is hard to see what is going on, it is equally hard to tell
whether Eco is manufacturing paradoxes and mysteries, or addressing them. But
this is not always the case, because, perhaps unwisely, he does engage,
confidently and combatively, with relatively clear themes of modern philosophy.
And here a more definite verdict is possible.
Prominent literary intellectuals often like to make
familiar reference to the technical terminology of mathematical logic or
philosophy of language. A friend of mine overheard the following conversation
in Cambridge during lÕaffaire Derrida, when the proposal to grant an honorary degree to
that gentleman met serious academic opposition in the university. A journalist
covering the fracas asked a Prominent Literary Intellectual what he took to be
Derrida's importance in the scheme of things. ÔWell,Õ the PLI confided
graciously, unblushingly, ÔGšdel showed that every theory is inconsistent
unless it is supported from outside. Derrida showed that there is no outside.Õ
Now, there are at least three remarkable things about
this. First, the thing that Gšdel was supposed to show could not possibly be
shown, since there are many demonstrably consistent theories. Second,
therefore, Gšdel indeed did not show it, and neither did he purport to do so.
Third, it makes no sense to say that an inconsistent theory could become
consistent by being Ôsupported from outsideÕ, whatever that might mean (inconsistency
sticks; you cannot get rid of it by addition, only by subtraction). So what
Derrida is said to have done is just as impossible as what Gšdel was said to
have done.
These mistakes should fail you in an undergraduate
logic or math or philosophy course. But they are minor considerations in the
world of the PLI. The point is
that the mere mention of Gšdel (like the common invocation of ÔhierarchiesÕ and ÔmetalanguagesÕ)
gives a specious impression of something thrillingly deep and thrillingly mathematical
and scientific (theory!
dazzling! Einstein!). And, not coincidentally, it gives the
PLI a flattering image of being something of a hand at these things, an
impresario of the thrills. I expect the journalist swooned.
Eco
is not in the same league as the PLI above. He has clearly taken the trouble to
read a good deal of modern philosophy of language. He talks familiarly of
Quine, Putnam, Davidson and Kripke. Perhaps the Anglo-American tradition should
be grateful for that, since few enough figures in continental Europe take this
trouble. He also talks intelligently of real problems for some positions in
that tradition, notably the problems of fictional and empty names. But there is
still a disturbing tendency for him to go right off the rails. I apologize in
advance for needing a little bit of detail to show this, but it is Eco who
strews the technicalities in the path of his audience.
A good example is EcoÕs use of the notion of Ôrigid
designationÕ. This is a technical term due to Saul Kripke, for a feature
belonging to names and indexical expressions (ÔthisÕ ÔIÕ, ÔhereÕ) in natural
languages, and distinguishing them from other referring expressions, notably
descriptions (Ôthe first dog born at seaÕ, ÔKantÕs home townÕ). In a nutshell,
the ÔrigidityÕ in question means that when you use a name, even to talk about
strange and different possibilities, you are still interpreted as talking about
whatever it is to which the name actually refers. So if I say, ÔHad the
political boundaries been slightly different, the people of Kšnigsberg might
have spoken Latvian,Õ I am still talking about that very town, Kšnigsberg. But
if I say, ÔHad his parents moved south, KantÕs home town might have been
Berlin,Õ the description ÔKantÕs home townÕ has become detached, as it were,
from Kšnigsberg. For I am not trying to say that had KantÕs parentÕs moved
south, Kšnigsberg might have been Berlin. I am saying that Berlin is where he
might have been born and raised. This is what is meant by saying that
descriptions are not rigid, whereas names are.
Eco
talks much of rigid designation. Unfortunately he identifies it by the
ambiguous formula that a rigid designator refers to the same thing Ôin all
possible worldsÕ, and then takes that formula in the wrong sense, as meaning that
there is no possibility of the same name referring to something different. This
is actually a misunderstanding against which Kripke explicitly and clearly
warned, more than once. Given this misinterpretation, of course, the idea of
rigid designation would be outrageous, since you can always take a term and use
it to refer to something different. People like giving their pets names like
ÔAristotleÕ or ÔToscaniniÕ. It is particularly bizarre of Eco to think that
Kripke and the tradition following him failed to notice that the indexical
ÔthisÕ may refer to different things on different occasions. It would be as if
having said, ÔThis is a rose,Õ pointing to one flower, you could not go on to
say, ÔBut this is a daffodil,Õ pointing to another.
The blunder leads Eco to suppose that rigid
designation is Ôindependent of all knowledge or intention or belief on the
speakerÕs partÕ (p. 297, and see n. 17 to the chapter). It leads him to some
strained speculations about the reference of terms being fixed by the Divine
Mind or the Infinite Mind, as if it were God who forges the link between names
and things. It also leads him to misunderstand another celebrated episode in
modern philosophy of language. The philosopher Hilary Putnam once proposed a
Ôtwin-earthÕ thought experiment, in which we imagine an earth just like this
one, except that the stuff playing the role of water is some different
chemical, XYZ. We can imagine the
persons on twin-earth talking happily of ÔwaterÕ. Eco interprets Putnam as
proposing that persons on twin-earth would thereby be referring to water (H2O),
because he takes rigidity to imply this. Whereas PutnamÕs point was exactly the opposite, namely, that they would not
be, but would be referring to the stuff that surrounds them, XYZ, which is not
water (only a good substitute for it). Eco not only gets this wrong, but even
implies that Putnam is somehow inconsistent, having forgotten his own earlier
opposition to the idea that reference is fixed somehow by magic, by something
outside of us like a Divine Mind.
On another occasion Eco squares up to one of the most
famous papers in modern philosophy, ÔTwo Dogmas of EmpiricismÕ, written in
1951. In that paper, Quine attacked the entire positivist program as dependent
on two carefully described dogmas. Later, in 1973, in an almost equally famous
paper, ÔOn the Very Idea of a Conceptual SchemeÕ, Davidson claimed that even a
sanitized empiricism, free from QuineÕs two dogmas, depended on yet a third
dogma. Eco, of course, presents himself as knowing all this. ÔI am well awareÕ,
he writes on p. 256, Ôthat advocating the existence of observation sentences
independent of a general system of propositions was said by Davidson to be the
third dogma of empiricismÉÕ
The
problem is that it wasnÕt. That
was Quine's second
dogma of empiricism, the one that he called reductionism, and to which his
counter was that Ôour statements about the external world face the tribunal of
sense experience not individually but only as a corporate bodyÕ. Davidson's third dogma of empiricism was that there is a
defensible dualism of Ôscheme and contentÕ, or, in other words, a distinction
between, on the one hand, the world waiting to be organized, and, on the other
hand, the conceptual scheme that does the organizing. And, like Kripke,
Davidson explicitly insisted on the distinction in the course of introducing
his third dogma.
Anyone
can make a slip, but I suspect Eco could not bring himself to face DavidsonÕs
third dogma fairly and squarely, since he is heavily invested in it himself,
constantly speculating on how the mind uses categories, schemata, cognitive
types, language and inference in order to organize and impose order on an
undifferentiated ÔcontinuumÕ. Or perhaps an ability to misread is encouraged by
semiotics. There are other examples: I would have liked to add a description of
EcoÕs nightmarish attempt to engage with Tarski, but that is not suitable for
family enjoyment.
VI
Does all this matter? To anyone who knows anything about Kripke,
Putnam, Quine, or Davidson, these things seem like the thirteenth strike of the
clock, the one that casts doubt on all the rest. But Eco brushes the details
aside, and his intended audience is unlikely to be any the wiser. In the wider
scheme of things, some might think that it doesnÕt really matter if here and
there a PLI goes astray. If all you want to do when you have the stick is to
twirl it around in the carnival, then it is not important whether you get hold
of the wrong end of it. So whatever else it may be, EcoÕs playfulness is certainly
a good defensive posture. It makes it hard for the critic to take a stand, and
harder still for the audience to admit that any shortcoming may be involved in
its admiration of the work. You cannot effectively criticize the Alice books on the grounds that they make no
sense, for this is part of their charm. But in EcoÕs case the lapses of sense
are not part of the charm. His words are presented as if to be taken seriously,
as a contribution to a little bit of science, a modest chamber in the storehouse
of valuable human thought. And they may be so taken by many, including in large
part their author.
The problem here is not the hip, glib, parodic, style
of a postmodernism that has fundamentally nothing to say. But it has similar
roots. In a famous review in the philosophical journal Mind in 1961, the biologist Sir Peter Medawar
talked of the perfectly bogus nature of Teilhard de ChardinÕs The Phenomenon
of Man and asked how it
could ever have gained an audience. He perceptively identified the state of mind
expressed as ÔReally itÕs beyond my poor brain, but doesnÕt that just show how profound and important it must be?Õ
This is an intellectual version of passive-aggressive syndromes in psychology,
an attitude also like that of taking pride in oneÕs own abasement. The novice
is to trust the master all the more because the master humiliates him, but his
trust in the master numbers him with the elect.
The comparison with the novitiate is telling. Until we
make it, we might be merely irritated by some of the more overt discourtesies
of EcoÕs book. He provides no translations of other languages, and Latin
especially is strewn around liberally. His book is marketed as a trade book,
not as a specialist monograph. Yet it presumes that the reader is acquainted with
things such as PeirceÕs philosophical terminologyÑsomething that almost nobody
understandsÑand, as we have seen, it presumes an acquaintance with difficult
and technical logic and philosophy of language. Eco also makes an unappetizing
number of back references to his own previous works and skirmishes with fellow
semioticians. Very, very few readers will not be insidiously humiliated. And we
can now see that this is deliberate, like the hazing routines in a fraternity
or the military. The audience for a book like this must want to enjoy its own
bewilderment. At the same time, however, the audience is not supposed to think
of this as playtime. It is not like the model audience of the Alice books, which might enjoy its own
confusion, just because it enjoys testing the boundaries of ordinary logic and
ordinary courses of events. The model audience for Carroll has to be
perceptive, in a way that the model audience of Teilhard de Chardin or of Eco
must be blind. Theirs cannot be an audience educated into thinking. It must
take active pleasure in the sleep of reason and take comfort in the presence of
mysteries.
It is important to realize that the fault has almost
nothing at all to do with one school of philosophy rather than another. After
all, Eco is marvelously eclectic. Nor does it have anything to do with the
alleged right of the intellectual to imitate the scientist, by adopting
technical terms and difficult vocabularies. The suffocation I have mentioned is
not usually due to difficult vocabularies. Yet Eco can leave you for pages
distressed or infuriated because you do not know if he has got hold of a real
problem, or what he is really trying to say about it. The fault, I believe, is
a kind of conceit or a knowingness. It is a complacency that blurs the difference
between genuine mastery of a technique and a self-deceived appearance of it.
So, when I finished reading the book, I had a recurring image of the Roadrunner
cartoons, in which the character Wile E. Coyote is forever finding himself
running off the edge of the cliff. And it just doesnÕt matter. He stays up, so
long as he keeps running, and doesnÕt look down. Eco never looks down. And if
he refuses to notice the cliff, perhaps he can judge rightly that his audience
will not notice it either. In this, like the platypus, he has perhaps adapted
himself perfectly to a particular environment. But in this case that should
make us deeply worried about the environment.
6, 150 words
Simon Blackburn
Chapel Hill, December 1999.