Contributions to
Philosophy: From Enowning
. Trans. Parvis Enad and Kenneth Maly. Bloomington: Indiana University press,
369pp. $39.50.
If you are a believer, Martin Heidegger was an unparalleled modern
thinker, whose profound diagnoses of the condition of mankind in the twentieth
century rightly dominated large tracts of culture, and directed the finest
subsequent work in the humanities. If you are not, he is a dismal windbag,
whose influence has been a total disaster, and whose affinity with the Nazis merely
indicates the vacuum where, in most other philosophers, there would have been a
combination of common sense and rudimentary decency.
Neither view allows much compromise. But it was not
always so. Shortly after Being and Time was published in 1927, the level-headed and later
hard-boiled Oxford philosopher Gilbert Ryle wrote a long, penetrating, and
moderately admiring review of it in the philosophical journal Mind. Ryle highlighted the influence of Husserl
and Brentano in the work. Husserl, especially, had developed the technique of
Òphenomenological analysisÓ, which approached traditional problems of mind and
body, perception and knowledge, by concentrating upon states of mind and their
objects. Since all human knowledge involves some state of mind, this subject
could claim a philosophically basic position. The question, however, is one of
the right method for isolating what is essential to states of mind in the first
place. There is a danger of collapsing the whole world into the world of
consciousness, or in other words, the danger of idealism.
The early Heidegger attempted to overcome residual
traces of idealism in the work of Husserl, by denying any split between
consciousness and its objects. This is an orthodox and reputable philosophical
project. But eradicating this split meant, in HeideggerÕs view, abandoning
almost all the vocabulary anyone might use to talk about the mind or the world.
It meant returning to the primeval springs of Meaning and Being unencumbered by
the terminology of philosophy, science, or everyday life, and starting
afresh. We should no longer think
in terms of a self, as owner of experiences, and the separate and independent
things around the self in space and time. We need to recover a lost primordial
unity in which such divisions did not exist. We are to do this, in phenomenology, by Òout-staringÓ the
phenomena, until in a moment of intuition their meaning-for-us is revealed.
In HeideggerÕs opinion, normal consciousness,
expressed with the inherited vocabulary of common sense, sees things Òonly with
a squintÓ, as Ryle puts it. The primary consciousness on the other hand is
consciousness of the world we live in as agents. It is an awareness of what we
are about. So, for instance, our primary awareness of objects is as things Òto
hand,Ó ready to use. Living in this awareness is what Heidegger calls caring.
In this kind of living the ÒscientificÓ split between mind and body, self and
world, vanishes. It is not very clear, in Being and Time, how this happens: as Ryle says, the
result smells a little oddly both of the pragmatism of William James and the
mysticism of Eckhart or St. Augustine.
Ryle noted an alarming tendency towards
unintelligibility, even in HeideggerÕs early work. But at the time
phenomenology was not sharply separated from other philosophy, either on the
continent or in the Anglo-American tradition. Husserl, for instance, was
carefully studied by Bertrand Russell. Phenomenological technique demands a serious concentration on the
nature of lived experience. The same could be said not only of all philosophy,
but also of literature and poetry, and it is no accident that the best-known
results of the method are the literary works of Sartre or Camus rather than the
philosophical work of, for example, Merleau-Ponty, valuable though that is. But
Heidegger went in a very different direction. He drifted away from the
connection with phenomenology, just as he repudiated Husserl, in order to
develop himself neither as a philosopher nor as a poet, but as an oracle.
So the present book is a translation, into something
fairly remote from English, of later philosophical notebooks that Heidegger
wrote, in something not quite German. The distance from English is greater than
the distance from German, not only because English is more resistant to the
encrustations of philosophical German but also because the translators seem to
enjoy trampling on this fact. The title itself illustrates the problem. The
German Òvom EreignisÓ would have translated into English Òfrom happeningÓ, or Òon
happeningÓ. ÒEreignisÓ itself lacks any connotations of Òtaking possession,Ó
which presumably would be what ÒenownÓ would suggest, were it a word of
English, which it isnÕt. Although the waters rise further when we are
instructed to strip the word ÒownÓ of any connotation connected with
possession, which is not entirely easy to do. They threaten to drown us altogether when we find that
almost any English verb will accept the prefix ÒenÓ: throughout the text some
things are enthought, while others enquiver, enbeckon, ensuffer, and encleave.
What seems to be random hyphenation further dislocates, or dis-locates, any
sense of being at home, or being-at-home, with the words on the page. Sometimes
this results in unintended comedy: Heidegger is fond of saying that things we
cannot do anything about are thrown at us, and for some pages this leads to
talk of a Òfree-throwÓ, giving the surprising impression that the topic is a
ball game.
However, the translators do present a defence:
Since no one has the slightest idea how Contributions would have looked had Heidegger smoothed out its syntax, no one has any idea of the measure by which to ÒreproachÓ him for the present shape of this work.
They go on to quote approvingly another believer:
It is not a question of reproaching Heidegger or of demanding posthumously different ways of behaving. Rather, it is we who come after him who are put to the test because of our access to his Nachlass and to all of his works.
Here is faith indeed. Notice particularly the term ÒreproachÓ, whose
slightly droopy overtones are hardly adequate, I should have thought, to
describing the more robust reactions of unbelievers.
For
the writing here is startling whatever your prior view of Heidegger. Open any
page and you are apt to find something like this:
Time-space is the enowned encleavage of the turning trajectories of enowning, of the turning between belongingness and the call, between abandonment by being and enbeckoning (the enquivering of the resonance of be-ing itself!).
Cleavage, at least, is defined for us:
The cleavage is the inner, incalculable settledness of en-ownment; of the essential swaying of be-ing as the midpoint that is used and that grants belonging Ð the midpoint that continues to be related to the passing of god and the history of man at the same time.
As already indicated, en-ownment might give trouble, but:
The enowning of en-ownment gather within itself the de-cision (Ent-scheidung): that freedom, as the ground that holds to abground, lets a distress emerge from out of which, as from out of the overflow of the ground, gods and man come forth into partedness.
Whatever the merits of phenomenology, by the time we get to this they
seem to have evaporated. Instead of a close focus on the nature of experience
we are given a constant, misty sense of uplift, with god and history and
resonance and Being all floating up alongside us. Nothing is said in such
sentences that could be verified or falsified, or assessed in any way as
plausible or not.
Yet this lack of content may not even be counted as a
flaw, for Heidegger actually instructs us at one point: ÒMaking itself
intelligible is suicide for philosophy.Ó
The real point of the writing is different. It becomes
apparent when we notice the constant repetitions: ÒHow can distress be effected
as distress?Ó ÒEnownment always means enowning as en-ownment.Ó ÒThe ground that
is the abground and is the ground of godsÕ lacking the ground.Ó ÒBe-ing of such
essential swaying is itself unique in this essential sway.Ó The truth, then, is that we have what
even HeideggerÕs respectful biographer, RŸdiger Safransky, describes as a
series of mantras. The work is to be a litany or a rosary, or a barrel-organ.
As Theodor Adorno put it, in The Jargon of Authenticity, the effect is to be that Òone speaks from
a depth which would be profaned if it were called content.Ó We have an attempt
to create a prophetic aura or mood. We have something that aspires to be a
religious work. ÒBeing,Ó we are to realize, Òis the trembling of Godding.Ó Oh,
goody!
II
To understand what is going on, I believe, you need to know a story.
Perhaps it is the story
Ð the primal story. It tells of a primordial golden age, when man was united
with himself, with his fellow man, and with nature (home, hearth, earth,
fatherland, paradise, shelter, innocence, wholeness, integration). Then there was a fall, when primitive
innocence and unity were destroyed and replaced by something worse (separation,
dissonance, fracture, strife, estrangement, alienation, anxiety, distress,
death, despair, nothing). To cure this state a road or journey is needed
(pilgrimage, stations, way or Weg, Bildung, action, will, destiny). The way may need a leader,
and the leader is the philosopher of PlatoÕs myth, who first ascends from the
shadows of the cave to the sunshine above (seer, prophet, poet, hero). There is
a crisis, and then a recovery of primordial unity itself (encounter, epiphany,
authenticity, transcendence, apocalypse, consummation, marriage, jubilation).
This may end the story, at its beginning, or the path may spiral on upwards,
its travellers fortified by the necessary sufferings of the journey.
In the story, the world, and life itself, need
interpretation, because they are the unfolding of a script, the writing of the
world-spirit (tidings, message, hermeneutics). And the whole drama is figured
not just in the life of an individual, but in universal history, or at least
the history of the race. The story is a history of Prometheus or Hyperion, or
the Prodigal, or Pilgrim, or the Artist, and it is also a history of the
evolution of Man or of Dasein, or of the Geister.
This is of course only the template of a story, or to
change the metaphor, it is a music that needs different orchestration at
different times. It can be given a
conventional religious tone, or a purely subjective one, as with inner-light
Protestant mysticism, or for that matter with Shelley or Blake. It can take a
nationalistic political setting, or a private and personal setting. The fall
may come with knowledge, which involves naming and separating and introducing
differences. It can come as it came to Israel, through other lapses, such as
the breaking of a covenant, or perhaps it came through the invention of
capitalism. The hero who leads to the light may be Augustine or Rimbaud, a
saint or a decadent.
The music was played loudly more than a century before
Heidegger, by Schelling and Schiller, Novalis and Hegel. England took it in
through Coleridge and the Romantics, America through Emerson, Whitman, and eventually
Hollywood. Even in one artist
expressions of the theme can range from the sublime to the ridiculous, from Tintern
Abbey to what a critic of
WordsworthÕs called the namby-pamby of the Lesser Celandine. It takes genius to
play the Romantic music without falsifying it, and perhaps even greater genius
to play it with a religious tremolo.
HeideggerÕs claim to genius was allowed because he
grafted onto phenomenology a vague version of the primal story. He celebrates
the primordial unity, which like many German Romantics he associates with
Greece, and which for some private reason he locates among the Presocratic
philosophers. He laments the fall that has plagued philosophy, science, and
everyday life ever since. And he promises the ecstatic recovery that sets
eternity into time, the mystical moment in which, as his favorite poet
Hšlderlin said, Òthe imperishable is present within us.Ó In the end the
romantic epiphany is to be consummated, the false categorizations of fallen
nature are lifted, and wordlessly the seer confronts the underlying realities
of Being. But, heavens, the dangers on the way! For Heidegger is clear that
there are risks and perils in attempting to eyeball Being. Wrestling,
venturing, confronting, colliding, seized, and always alone, what a hero he is,
this fearless Wanderer above the Seas of Mist!
To the agnostic eye the first curiosity in all this is
that the execution of the phenomenological method falls considerably short of
the promise. For just one example, and from the earlier, less messianic period,
consider again our relationship to things around us. Allegedly, primordial
artisans treat things around them as things to use, whereas scientific thought
treats things as objects in space-time. To-handedness (the artisanÕs concept)
is close to Dasein, whereas present-at-handedness (things as thought of
scientifically) is distant from real human life. So the first, Zuhandenseinheit, can be announced as Òprimary form of beingÓ compared
to the second, mere, superficial scientific Vorhandenseinheit. The first is primordial, the second
derivative and falsifying, suitable only for rude mechanicals like Newton. Some
have speculated that this captures an essential insight of pragmatism, although
HeideggerÕs distaste for all things scientific sits uneasily with that. But the
vital point is that the jargon only conceals a shocking lack of focus in the
original thought. For is it not obvious that an artisan who is about a piece of
carpentry does not see a hammer as a tool as opposed to seeing it as an item in space and
time? It is only because he sees it as an enduring object with a
location, shape, inelasticity, and mass that he sees it as zuhanden at all. Things not seen as having these
desirable properties cannot be seen as usable for driving nails.
This is a
trivial example of a fuzziness or vacuity even in the earlier work, and that
balloons in Contributions.
The theologian Karl Jaspers wrote of Heidegger, ÒAmong contemporaries the most
exciting thinker, masterful, compelling, mysterious Ð but then leaving you
empty-handed.Ó The mantras are not expressions of some achieved vision or
experience or emotion, but instructions to work one up. They are not the
records of a pilgrimage, but a prospectus into which you can inscribe your own
detail. The orchestra is only tuning up. So, in the last part of the work under
review, when Heidegger presents himself as a prophet out of his time, yet
prefiguring the Way for the Ones Who Are To Come, few unbelievers will be
reminded of Blake, or even Nietzsche. It sounds utterly trite, more like the
script for Obi-Wan Kenobi in Star Wars.
HeideggerÕs faithful may not mind the charge that he leaves us
empty-handed, just as he himself heads off complaints about intelligibility.
Safransky relates that the physicist von WeizsŠcker told Heidegger the story
about a man who spent all his days in a tavern. Asked why, he replied that it
was his wife: she talks and talks and talks. ÒWhat does she talk about?Ó ÒAh,
that she doesnÕt say.Ó Heidegger is supposed to have replied ÒYes, that is how
it is.Ó
If this was a moment of self-knowledge, it cannot have
lasted long. In the jargon of authenticity, saying nothing means saying
Nothing, and this has a much better ring to it. Saying Nothing requires
confronting the very source of care (Sorge) itself. It means battling the mechanical age for
what it is, gazing into the abyss, (en)quivering with the resonances of the
void. It takes the poet-philosopher-hero to do it. Only the inauthentic, the
dwellers in the shadows, could find that saying Nothing is a disappointment.
And that could not be a
criticism, since dis-appointment is just what you should expect when your
appointment with Being is not yet due. The knowledge of the
philosopher-poet-hero is different:
This knowing can never be communicated and disseminated like the knowledge of what is extant. Those who bring it to one another must already go in the crossing in that they, intimating decisions come unto one another and yet do not meet.
Note the Biblical
resonances. The dwellers in the shadows by contrast
drag what is ownmost down into what is intelligible and, by such dragging, shove it into what is merely still tolerated and humored.
Occasionally, however, Heidegger did put his head back in the cave and
talk in normal language. When he did so, the results of the wrestling matches
and collisions with Being turned out to be a little disappointing. Here is his
own version of unity with nature, in a passage quoted by Adorno:
Recently I got a second invitation to the University of Berlin. On such an occasion I leave the city and go back to my cabin. I hear what the mountains and woods and farmyards say. On the way I drop in on my old friend, a seventy-five-year-old farmer. He has read in the newspaper about the Berlin invitation. What will he say? He slowly presses the sure glance of his clear eyes against mine, holds his mouth tightly closed, lays his faithful and cautious hand on my shoulder Ð and almost imperceptibly shakes his head. That means: absolutely No!
I like this true man of the Volk, so closely resembling Adam Lambsbreath in Cold
Comfort Farm, Òlinked to
all dumb brutes by a chain forged in soil and sweatÓ: the Swabian peasant as
golden retriever. Mind you, gnarly old dog though he be, he still reads university
tittle-tattle in the newspapers. They didnÕt do that around Grasmere.
Heidegger undoubtedly convinced audiences that his was
the voice of Being. There is ample evidence of the charisma he could exercise,
through sublime self-confidence and messianic self-presentation. The effect is
beautifully dissected in a remarkable paper in the Journal of Philosophy in 1938, in which Marjorie Glicksman, who
attended HeideggerÕs lectures in the nineteen-thirties, records his procedures.
She describes the vituperative denunciations of previous philosophers, and
HeideggerÕs own repeated claims to uniqueness and greatness. Above all, she
describes the aristocratic immunity of those on the summits to criticism from
the dwellers in the shadows below, who include any spokesmen for science,
history, logic and common sense:
It should be added, perhaps, that the forcefulness of HeideggerÕs ÒaristocraticÓ arguments depends in large part on the personality of the lecturer. One is caught as in a political rally by the slow intensity of his speech. The contemptuous epigrams with which he dismisses the protests of logic or good sense sting the listenerÕs ears with their acidity; and his prophetic solemnity when he invokes the quest for being ties one as spellbound as if one were taking his first step into the rituals of the Eleusinian mysteries.
IV
Much has been written about the supposed relationship between
HeideggerÕs philosophy and his nineteen-thirtiesÕ support for the Third Reich.
Hans Sluga has shown that there was nothing unusual about HeideggerÕs politics
at the time. Many philosophers in Germany subscribed to a quartet of doctrines
that made them sympathetic to the National Socialists. They believed that
theirs was a time of moral crisis; that the crisis was particular to Germany
and needed to be solved in Germany; that the solution called for acts of will
directed by a great leader; and that the result would be orderÑa new order that
would last a thousand years.
None of these could be called implications of
HeideggerÕs philosophy, for where there is no certain content there are no
certain implications. But they make up one way of inscribing detail into the
prospectus that he offers. Each doctrine is closely allied to the Romantic
worldview, and indeed would be impossible without it. Many of the words I
picked out as thematic in Romanticism fit naturally into this quartet. The
themes are all there: lost unity, the need for a redemptive journey, the
visionary leader, and the goal of a vague and unspecified recovery of what has
been lost. National Socialism was one way of orchestrating the primal melody.
Contributions
to Philosophy was written
between 1936 and 1938, when Heidegger had ended his active engagement in
politics. If, as Safransky describes, in his earlier rectoral address to the
University of Freiburg, he Òpulls out all the stops of his penny-dreadful
romanticism to lend events an unsuspected profundity,Ó here the tone is
different. The philosophical fantasies are detached from National Socialist
politics. Heidegger no longer marches his SS-uniformed students out from
Freiburg to evangelical camps where they can commune with the hills, and
meadows, and doggy peasants, of the Fatherland. Rather, he Òinscribes himself
in the history of Being as a herald who arrived too early, and is therefore in
danger of being crushed and rejected by his time.Ó National Socialism is no
longer seen as the way to reunite Germany with the world of the Presocratics.
There is too much science and engineering, and too little communion with the
sources of Being.
Nevertheless, it is worth remembering that the beast
was only sleeping. Jaspers had a Jewish wife, and his relations with Heidegger
after the war were naturally wary. Yet Heidegger, astonishingly, wrote to
Jaspers in 1952 that the cause of evil was not yet at an end, and that in such
a state of homelessness an ÒadventÓ was to be expected Òwhose further hints we
may perhaps still experienceÉÓ. Even the worshipful Jaspers, himself an adept
at vague religiosity, recoiled
from this crassness:
does not a philosophy that surmizes and poetizes in such phrases in your letter, a philosophy that aroused the vision of the monstrous, once more prepare the ground for the victory of totalitarianism by severing itself from reality?Ó
He was absolutely right to ask the question, and he never got an
answer.
V
So why is Heidegger still
an influence, when infinitely more readable philosophers, and literary
philosophers such as Sartre, are not? We should be careful here, for outside a
very few pockets, Heidegger is not really an influence in Anglo-American
professional philosophy, where the view that it is suicide for philosophy to be
intelligible is not popular. His influence is mainly continued in the more
debilitated parts of the academy. The legacy is nicely exhibited on the web at http://www.elsewhere.org/cgi-bin/postmodern/.
Here you can read an original essay, different on every visit, written by The
Postmodernist Generator, a program due to a student in the Monash University
Department of Computer Science and Òmodified slightly by Pope Dubious
Provenance XI using the Dada Engine, a system for generating random text from
recursive grammars.Ó The Dada Engine is not quite calibrated to 1930s Heidegger
Ñits lexicon is proper English, for exampleÑbut one senses how easily it could
be.
Still, there is the question of how it happened and
goes on happening. Perhaps the primal story is so potent that just using one of
the words that suggest it turns lead to gold. Even nihilism and despair grip us
mainly because, in our minds, we hear the lost music, and mourn at what might
have been. At the faintest sound of the melody people drop their everyday way
of being and dance to the enchantment. It is, after all, an enchantment into
which you can read almost anything. Heidegger can be an icon for the Nazi, the
priest, or the hippie. He may be a defender of the faith, a poet-philosopher
for the Society of Jesus, or the nay-sayer whose rejection of modern mechanical
life is a timely, authentic, update of that of Carlyle or Ruskin. He can be a
pragmatist, or the enemy of dreary technology. And all you have to do is to
accept the prospectus, and write your own script. You must not mind drowning,
and you may need to leave behind any tinge of common sense, science, logic,
history, or reason Ð but these are easy burdens to shed in difficult times. In
any event, like any good salvationist, he has already instructed you to do it,
both by precept and by example.
Analytical philosophy is sometimes contrasted
unfavorably with ÒContinentalÓ philosophy, because of its supposed lack of
political and moral weight. If this charge was ever just, it has long ceased to
be so. Indeed, to critics such as Richard Posner, modern Anglo-American
philosophy is at fault for being too moralistic, disrespectfully trespassing on
the domain of economists and judges. What I think is true is that analytical
philosophy is profoundly mistrustful of sustaining myths, including the primal
story. We resist the pipes of Pan, because we care about truth. And
intelligibility is a precondition of truth. If you cannot tell whether a string
of words says anything, you cannot tell whether it says anything true. This is
not a parochial or superficial matter. The choice of truth above fog is one
that anybody who deserves calling a philosopher has to make, although it will
set them at odds with a politics, from either left or right, that can only
survive in a fog. Fortunately, even in HeideggerÕs perturbed times, there were
those who saw this. We can recall
the contemporary words of the Italian philosopher Benedetto Croce:
I have now at last read the whole of HeideggerÕs address, which is stupid and servile at the same time. I am not surprised at the success his philosophizing will have for some time Ð the vacuous and general is always successful. But it produces nothing. I too believe that he will have no effect on politics, but he dishonors philosophy, and that is a pity also for politics, especially future politics.
Simon Blackburn
Simon Blackburn is the Edna J. Koury Distinguished Professor of
Philosophy at the University of North Carolina, Chapel Hill. His introduction
to philosophy, Think is
published by Oxford University Press.
4220 words